Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 7

Cage and Philosophy

Author(s): Noël Carroll


Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 52, No. 1, The Philosophy of
Music (Winter, 1994), pp. 93-98
Published by: Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/431588
Accessed: 22-09-2019 05:41 UTC

REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
https://www.jstor.org/stable/431588?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

The American Society for Aesthetics, Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

This content downloaded from 130.70.8.131 on Sun, 22 Sep 2019 05:41:00 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
NOEL CARROLL

Cage and Philosophy

The influence of the late John Cage extends in poses to his compositions.4 Cage's philosophi-
many directions, affecting not only musical cally motivated musical practice, in turn, was to
practice and the theory of composition, but rivet aesthetic attention to sound as such. That
postmodem choreography, poetry, performance is: "New music: new listening. Not an attempt
art, and even philosophy. In this brief note, I to understand something that is being said, for
intend to explore Cage's relevance to philoso- if something were being said, the sounds would
phy. To this end, I shall examine Cage's own be given the shapes of words. Just attention to
philosophy of music and conclude with some the activity of sounds."5
remarks about the significance of Cage's proj- Of the programmatical importance of em-
ect for the philosophy of art in general. phasizing or foregrounding sound as such as
Cage, of course, has left us a large body of the object of audience attention, Cage claims:
writing. Even if he did not think that his music
"said" anything, he surrounded it with a great ... I said that since the sounds were just sounds, this
deal of doctrine, freighting his experiments gave people hearing them the chance to be people,
with aesthetic, moral, and political relevance. centered within themselves where they actually are,
Much of the writing is polemical, animated by not off artificially in the distance as they are accus-
a philosophical conception of music, or, as he tomed to be, trying to figure out what is being said by
would prefer to call it, of the "organization of some artist by means of sounds. Finally I said that
sound."' Of sound, Cage asserts: the purpose of this purposeless music would be
achieved if people learned to listen; that when they
A sound does not view itself as thought, as ought, as listened they might discover that they preferred the
needing another sound for its elucidation, as etc.; it sounds of everyday life to the ones they would pres-
has not time for any consideration-it is occupied ently hear in the musical program; that that was
with the performance of its characteristics: before it alright as far as I was concerned.6
has died away it must have made perfectly exact its
frequency, its loudness, its length, its overtone struc- Put in the idiom that is increasingly popular
ture, the precise morphology of these and of itself.2 nowadays, Cage construes what the tradition
identifies as musical sounds to be "privileged."
For Cage, what we call music ought to be sound He, in response, is concerned to dethrone them.
as such, bereft of anything we might be tempted Moreover, this ambition seems underwritten by
to call "meaning." the sense that the distinction between music
He says that "I imagine that as contemporary and sound (or noise) portends a deeper divi-
music goes on changing in the way that I'm sion, namely one that divorces the listener from
changing it what will be done is to more and the world. Here it is useful to contrast Cage's
more completely liberate sounds from abstract view with Schopenhauer's. It was Schopen-
ideas and more exactly to let them be physically hauer's conviction that music was the highest
uniquely themselves."3 And along with es- art just because it bore the least relation to the
chewing the association of abstract ideas, Cage everyday world of appearances. But for Cage,
explicitly rejects attributions of themes or pur- insofar as the distinction between music and

The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 52:1 Winter 1994

This content downloaded from 130.70.8.131 on Sun, 22 Sep 2019 05:41:00 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
94 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

noise is another instance of the dichotomy ignored, while, at other times, he is wont to
between art and the world, it warrants dis- speak more generically of beauty.10
solution.7 Thus, he approvingly quotes Jas- Part and parcel of Cage's brief against the
per Johns's remark that "I can imagine a soci- musical tradition of the West is his insistence
ety without any art at all, and it is not a bad that the sounds that he foregrounds neither say
society."8 anything nor do they have a purpose. Cage ap-
One of Cage's key strategies for dissolving pears to believe this is because chance opera-
these homologous dichotomies is to foreground tions pre-empt the direct operation of the will
noise-sometimes naturally occurring noise, on his material. This makes its interpretation in
sometimes musical (but decontextualized as in terms of authorial intention impossible, for the
Hymns and Variations). In Imaginary Landscape artist no longer has the means to express herself
No. 4, the "instruments" are twelve radios, or to realize intended purposes. Paraphrasing
tuned according to random procedures. This Susan Sontag, an aesthetician obviously under
results in a melange with neither discernible the influence of Cage, we might say that the
structure nor comprehensive sense, thereby pu- composition just is; it does not convey a mean-
tatively reducing attention to the humanly pro- ing to be interpreted; it exists as a sensuous
duced sounds as just sounds. Likewise, in the presence that engages our attention, rather than
self-explanatory Demonstration of the Sounds our interpretive capacities."
of the Environment, three hundred people si- According to Sontag and Cage, Cage's sounds
lently follow an itinerary generated by aleatoric and Cage-inspired works such as those of
procedures derived from the I Ching. Of course, Yvonne Rainer in dance, and of Robert Morris
Cage's best-known piece in this genre is his and Larry Poons in fine art are on an ontologi-
4'33" in which silence is used as a notational cal par with ordinary sounds, ordinary move-
device, i.e., as a way of framing circumambient ments, and ordinary objects, like bathroom
sounds. In it, the performer opens the score, but sinks. Not only are they indiscernible from
plays nothing, compelling the audience-by mere real things, but they are said to lack what
subtraction, so to speak-to attend to whatever Arthur Danto calls aboutness.'2 That is, Cage
sounds happen in the interval of "silence." and his followers maintain that the objects and
In all these cases, Cage's goal is to design a events in question are semantically mute in pre-
context in which ex hypothesi, the audience is, cisely the way that mere real things and events
in a manner of speaking, encouraged, if not are not about anything. Ordinary objects and
coerced or reduced, to attending to the qualities events just are. And according to Cage, this is
of the sounds themselves for the simple reason also the condition of his sounds. Therefore, if
that the events have been constructed in such a these compositions are in fact on a par with
way that there is nothing else to which one everyday sound events-primarily in virtue of
could attend. On some occasions, Cage's po- their lack of meaning-then there will be no
lemical justification of these strategies reminds principled way of drawing a distinction between
one of the sloganeering of the early Russian them and everyday sound events. Thus, there
formalists. That is, his defamiliarizing strate- will be no way in which to place them in sepa-
gies, such as the use of chance composition and rate ontological categories like art or music.
silence as a notational device, enable us to lis- So the crux of the matter hinges on whether
ten to the world afresh.9 By being confronted, or not Cage and aestheticians like Sontag are
in other words, by sounds in a new way, we right in claiming that the works in question are
attend to qualities that heretofore went unno- mute, that they say nothing, that they are, even
ticed. But at other times, Cage is also apt to in an extended way of speaking, meaningless.
characterize the importance of foregrounding Surely, the intervention of automatic procedures
sound as such in the language of classical aes- of construction makes these works problematic
thetic theory. By refraining sound via nota- as examples of art under classical expression
tional silence, we are granted access to gener- theories of art.13 And it at least thwarts certain
ally unheeded beauties. Thus, at times Cage types of psychoanalytic interpretations of the
motivates attention to sound as an adventure in works. However, there are other ways in which
the perception of qualities that are customarily these works can be thought to bear meaning

This content downloaded from 130.70.8.131 on Sun, 22 Sep 2019 05:41:00 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Carroll Cage and Philosophy 95

such that we will argue that Cage's sounds can my invocation of exemplification with respect
be differentiated from mere real events. to Cage. For in the case of Cage, through his
Initially, I think that if we take Cage seri- strategies of framing, the referential require-
ously-which I maintain we should-then we ments for exemplification are clearly met. More-
must insist that the sounds Cage foregrounds in over, the concept of exemplification seems per-
works like 4'33" have a semantic dimension. fectly to match Cage's stated intentions. Thus,
For part of Cage's project is to bring it about- despite his polemics to the contrary, the semi-
by means of his composition-that we become nal works of Cage and of many of the artists he
attuned, so to say, to the richness, perhaps even influenced (especially in the sixties) are sym-
the aesthetic richness, of noise. But Cage's bolic. They are exercises in exemplification.19
noises, then, are not like everyday noise. They Cage's noise, then, does, given its pragmatic
have a semantic function. They are, to use context, say something and it does have a pur-
Nelson Goodman's terminology, exemplifica- pose: it illustrates something about sound and
tions of everyday noise-i.e., samples of every- its potential-something of especial autobio-
day noise-indeed samples which within a cer- graphical significance for Cage, given his
tain musicological context are supposed to avowal of his love of sound in his earliest child-
illustrate the latent potentials of noise.14 They hood memories.
are framed-in some cases by notational si- Of course, by emphasizing the importance of
lence-and that framing within the context of context for the intended operation of Cage's
musicological debate gives them a point. Point- noise, I have in mind not only the immediate
edly, they are symbols of noise, not abstract circumstances of his performances, but also the
symbols, but symbols as samples. historical context in which they are situated.
Ordinary noise in this sense is not a symbol One reason that I think that contemporary phi-
because ordinary noise is not framed. Ordinary losophers would disagree with Cage's claim
noise does not refer to anything. But Cage's that his music is meaningless is that many of
noise, given its staging, does refer to some- them have become convinced of the Wittgen-
thing: it refers to itself and in referring to itself
steinian notion that meaning is a function of the
in the way and in the context it does, it func- use of a word or a gesture within a context that
tions as a sample of ambient noise in general. It has a structure. When I raise my hand in a
possesses certain properties or qualities which classroom, that signals that I have something to
it exemplifies in a way that calls-and on Cage's say, not because raising one's hand has a natural
accounting is supposed to call-our attention to meaning but because in the context of the class-
congruent properties in other noises.15 Cage's room, given its rules, one uses hand raising to
noises are, in other words, illustrative. Thus, signal that one has something to say.
they have a semantic content or function that Now the artworld is not as structured in terms
the ordinary noises to which they allude lack.16 of rules as a classroom is. However, it does
One objection to Goodman's notion of exem- provide a context-specifically a tradition-in
plification is that Goodman seems willing to which certain gestures take on meaning. For
apply it in cases where the artworks in question example, at a time when verisimilitude was
seem to merely possess certain properties.17 thought to be objective, a logical space was
Thus, given Goodman's overall defense of the opened in which figural distortion could call
cognitive status of art,18-i.e., its role in map- forth associations of subjectivity. That distor-
ping the world and its properties-exemplifi- tion should go with subjectivity, rather than,
cation sometimes seems like a catchall symbol say, democracy, is a function of the frameworks
of last resort. But, it is argued, something does and constraints placed on our associations by
not exemplify, and, therefore, does not symbol- the pre-existing artistic context. A certain
ize simply by possessing a property: some ref- choice, when made in a given art-historical
erential (or self-referential) machinery must context, is going to get its point by being used
also be in place. in a context that itself has already been struc-
Nevertheless, even if this general criticism of tured by history. And that point, broadly speak-
Goodman's deployment of the concept of exem- ing, is its meaning; that point is the sort of thing
plification is accurate, it does not compromise that we mobilize interpretations to isolate.

This content downloaded from 130.70.8.131 on Sun, 22 Sep 2019 05:41:00 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
96 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Clearly, in this sense, Cage's work bears in- bols, indeed which show us a new world, or
terpretation. It is purposive and it has a point, which show us the world in a new light, or,
one that depends on it being meaningful or pur- perhaps, more aptly, sound us the world in new
posive activity within a certain context of tones.
debate. Earlier I discussed aspects of that con- Cage was certainly right to challenge the
text of debate, as has Cage in writings like view that art is divorced from the world. How-
"The Future of Music: Credo." But, we do not ever, he need not have gone so far as to argue
need to read Cage's writings in order to figure that in order to do this, his compositions had to
out the point of his work, if we are already be completely shorn of meaning. He did suc-
familiar with the context in which it serves elo- ceed in severing his particular sounds from
quently as a call broadening the range and rich- authorial intention in one sense. But it is not
ness of auditory experience. Likewise, where, clear that he severed his compositions from
as a participant in our musical culture, one is intentionality altogether. For his compositions
apprised of the almost inescapable pervasive- remain situated in a cultural space, one which
ness of the concept of artistic expression, one imbues gestures within it with purposes, and, as
easily comprehends the polemical thrust of we have seen, with semantic content and mean-
aleatoric techniques as contextually poignant ings, at least in a broad sense. The cultural con-
gestures of repudiation.20 text, that is, provides a matrix of meanings,
If one doubts the semantic content of Cage's which carry intentionality-a tradition which
noise, one need only recall the degree to which both constrains moves within it, and invests
these works depend on affronting entrenched genuine actions within it with meaning. If Cage
musical ideas. Using what might be called bour- says that his works like 4'33" lack meaning, it
geois taste as a straightman, Cage's aleatoric is because the compass of meaning that he has
techniques taunt; the ensuing outrage makes in mind is narrower than that countenanced by
the presence of communication unmistakable. many contemporary philosophers of art.
Nor is the indignation inarticulate in the way On the other hand, it is exactly the perplex-
that a response to a slap on the face might be. ities of the Cagean aesthetic that forced con-
Those offended know precisely what is at stake temporary philosophers to begin to rethink the
theoretically. This is apparent when they say, accepted boundaries of meaning and interpre-
"But anyone could do that." tation. Furthermore, if my analysis is correct so
In virtue of their historical context, Cage's far, it may also be instructive about changes in
compositions have a subject. Indeed, they have the temper of theoretical activity between the
more than one. They are about something, in fifties and sixties, on one side, and the seven-
part by way of exemplification, and in part by ties and eighties, on the other side. Today, in
contextual (art-historical-conversational) im- many areas of thought, not only philosophy, we
plicature in conjunction with exemplification. are impressed by the extreme degree that most
For example, they are about ordinary sound of what we encounter is culturally charged and,
and the contrast between ordinary sound and in that sense, meaningful. In the fifties and
(traditionally) musical sound. Indeed, through early sixties, attentiveness to the cultural and
his ingenious intervention in the tradition of historical envelopment of virtually every aspect
music, Cage may well have created a new aes- of human activity was not in the forefront of
thetic category, that of ordinariness. Whereas our thinking in the same way. The difference
before Cage, the ordinary object figured in aes- that I have marked between Cage and recent
thetic discourse negatively-as a foil to the art philosophy of art bears testimony to the way in
object-Cage's noise functions to introduce a which we now find it difficult to conceive of
positive aesthetic predicate, ordinariness, culture, history and cultural meaning as not hav-
which focuses attention on a newly discovered ing bearing on almost everything we produce.
realm of value.21 That is, Cage's compositions I say this not in order to disparage Cage. That
provide us with a new symbol with which to his philosophy of music is a creature of its mo-
organize the world. They are not only mean- ment is something that we should expect. But,
ingful in the sense of having a purpose; they are at the same time, through his practice, he paved
meaningful in the sense of being symbols, sym- the way for a more contextual philosophy of art

This content downloaded from 130.70.8.131 on Sun, 22 Sep 2019 05:41:00 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Carroll Cage and Philosophy 97

by challenging the conception that artworks tinues to use the language of beauty, I am not convinced
that he is as radical as Daniel Herwitz claims and, there-
exist in splendid isolation from the world.
fore, I am not persuaded that Cage's supposed skepticism
Cage's work opened art to the environmental merits the refutation that Herwitz deals it in his "The Secu-
surround, which, in turn, prefigured an appre- rity of the Obvious."
ciation of the cultural and historical surround. 11. See Susan Sontag, "Against Interpretation," in her
Against Interpretation (New York: A Delta Book, 1966).
As well, without bold conjectures like Cage's
For criticism of Sontag's view, see Noel Carroll, "Trois
that his sounds said nothing, it would have been
propositions pour une critique de la danse contemporaine,"
less likely that philosophers would have strug- in La Danse au Dgfi, ed. Michele Febvre (Montreal: Para-
gled with questions of how such artworks man- chute, 1987).

age to have meanings, to be about things, to 12. See Arthur Danto, The Transfiguration of the Com-
monplace (Harvard University Press, 1981), especially
speak to us. Thus, in the recent dialectic within
Chapter 1.
the philosophy of art, John Cage alerted the 13. It is interesting to note that Louis Mink has sketched
community to some of our most important a way in which work like Cage's might be accommodated
issues.22 within the framework of a new sort of expression theory.
See his overlooked article: "Art Without Artists," in Liber-
ations: New Essays On The Humanities in Revolution, ed.
NOEL CARROLL
Ihab Hassan (Wesleyan University Press, 1972), pp. 70-86.
Department of Philosophy 14. See Nelson Goodman, Languages of Art (Indianapo-
University of Wisconsin-Madison lis and New York: The Bobbs-Merrill Company, 1968),
Madison, Wisconsin 53706 pp. 52-71; and Nelson Goodman, Ways of Worldmaking
(Indianapolis: Hackett Publishers, 1985), pp. 63-70.
15. The jargon of properties, here, is, of course, my own
and not Goodman's since Goodman ultimately rejects
1. John Cage, "The Future of Music: Credo," from his property-talk.
Silence (MIT Press, 1970), p. 3. 16. It is interesting to note that Cage begins Silence by
2. Cage, "Experimental Music: Doctrine," from Silence, saying that "My intention has been, often, to say what I had
p. 15. to say in a way that would exemplify it; that would, conceiv-
3. Quoted in Michael Nyman, Experimental Music: Cage ably, permit the listener to experience what I had to say
and Beyond (New York: Schirmer Books, 1974), p. 42. rather than just hear about it" [Emphasis added]. What I, of
4. Cage, "Experimental Music: Doctrine," p. 17. course, wish to claim is that this penchant for exemplifica-
5. Cage, "Experimental Music: Doctrine," p. 10. In a tion is a major underlying strategy in much of his work. See
recent article, Daniel Herwitz questions whether the uto- Silence, p. ix.
pian goal of attending to sound as such is possible. See 17. See, for example, Monroe C. Beardsley, "Semiotic
Daniel Herwitz, "The Security of the Obvious: On John Aesthetics and Aesthetic Education," in The Journal of
Cage's Musical Radicalism," in Critical Inquiry 14:4 (Sum- Aesthetic Education 9:3 (July 1975): 5-26.
mer 1984): 784-804. 18. For example, Goodman, Languages of Art, pp. 255-
6. In Die Reihe 5 (1959): 116. Quoted in Paul Griffiths, 265.
Modern Music: The Avant Garde Since 1945 (New York: 19. I have always been surprised by the fact that Good-
George Braziller, 1981), p. 124. man's notion of exemplification did not gain more critical
7. In M: Writings '67-'72, Cage, always the leveler, currency than it did. For whatever philosophical difficulties
writes "Classification ... ceases when it's no/longer possible Goodman's use of it may raise, it seems not only unprob-
to establish oppositions...." See p. 10. lematically but appositely suited to elucidate critically a
8. John Cage, "Forward," from his M: Writings '67-'72 great deal of contemporary art.
(Wesleyan University Press, 1973), n.p. 20. For a discussion of the notion of repudiation in the
9. See, for example, Victor Shklovsky, "Art as Tech- preceding paragraph, see Noel Carroll, "Art, Practice and
nique," in Russian Formalist Criticism: Four Essays, eds. Narrative," in The Monist 71 (1988): 140-156.
Lee T. Lemon and Marion J. Reis (University of Nebraska Also, I should explain that the reason that I refer above to
Press, 1965), especially p. 12. Cage's gestures of repudiation as "poignant" is that I
10. For example, Cage writes: "Beauty is now underfoot believe them to be ultimately self-refuting. The problem
wherever we take the trouble to look. (This is an American here that confronts Cage's attempts to say nothing by way
discovery)." See "On Robert Rauschenberg, Artist, and His of his noises is analogous to the problems that beset the
Work," in Silence, p. 98. Also, note the undeniably Kantian artist J. (for Jasper?) in the first chapter of Danto's Trans-
inflection of the following: "And what is the purpose of figuration of the Commonplace. Ironically, Cage, like J.,
writing music? One is, of course, not dealing with purposes winds up saying something while trying to say nothing.
but dealing with sounds. Or the answer must take the form And, again ironically, Cage, like J., says something in vir-
of a paradox: a purposeful purposelessness or a purposeless tue of the art theory he holds, which theory itself is contra-
play" [Emphasis added], Silence, p. 12. Cage also makes dicted by the very works he produces-works which are
autobiographical remarks about his own love of the beauty about something in the teeth of a theory that claims they
of sounds as a child. have no semantic content.
Furthermore, I should add, that insofar as Cage con- Though Cage's noise says quite a lot by my accounting, I

This content downloaded from 130.70.8.131 on Sun, 22 Sep 2019 05:41:00 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
98 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

do not believe that it can be thought of as propounding or DeKooning's boast that "The past does not influence me; I
advancing a theory. At best, Cage's noises emblematize or influence it." See Arthur Danto, "The Artistic Enfran-
exemplify theories, or, perhaps, introduce putative counter- chisement of Real Objects: The Artworld," in Aesthetics: A
examples to antecedently existing theories. For further Critical Anthology, eds. George Dickie and R.J. Sclafani
arguments supporting this conclusion, see Noel Carroll, (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1977), p. 34; John Cage,
"Contemporary Avant-garde Art and the Problem of The- "History of Experimental Music in the United States," in
ory," in The Adventures of the Avant-garde:from Dandyism Silence, p. 67; T.S. Eliot, "Tradition and the Individual
to Postmodernism, eds. Pellegrino D'Acierno and Barbara Talent," in Twentieth-Century Literary Theory, eds. Vassilis
Lekatsas (Westport, Ct.: Greenwood Press, forthcoming). Lambropoulos and David Neal Miller (State University of
21. This idea is related to Arthur Danto's idea of a style New York Press, 1987), p. 146.
matrix, though I part company with Danto's suggestion that 22. An earlier version of this paper was delivered as a
artists may bring it about that past artworks acquire new talk on 2/24/88 at Wesleyan University as part of a confer-
properties. Cage, himself, on the other hand, might endorse ence honoring Cage's achievements. I would also like to
the possibility, suggested by Danto and T.S. Eliot, of back- thank Peter Kivy for his suggestions regarding this article.
wards causation in art history. After all, Cage seems to like

This content downloaded from 130.70.8.131 on Sun, 22 Sep 2019 05:41:00 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

Вам также может понравиться