Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 18

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/224814459

Intuition in Judgment and Decision Making: Extensive Thinking Without Effort

Article  in  Psychological Inquiry · November 2010


DOI: 10.1080/1047840X.2010.517737

CITATIONS READS
107 1,245

2 authors:

Tilmann Betsch Andreas Glöckner


Universität Erfurt University of Cologne
98 PUBLICATIONS   2,403 CITATIONS    126 PUBLICATIONS   5,031 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

Child Decision Making View project

Perspective, Opinion, and Commentary Pieces View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Tilmann Betsch on 15 December 2015.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


This article was downloaded by: [Universitats Forschungsbiblio]
On: 24 November 2011, At: 07:00
Publisher: Psychology Press
Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House,
37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

Psychological Inquiry
Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:
http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/hpli20

Intuition in Judgment and Decision Making: Extensive


Thinking Without Effort
a b
Tilmann Betsch & Andreas Glöckner
a
Department of Psychology, University of Erfurt, Erfurt, Germany
b
Max Planck Institute for Research on Collective Goods, Bonn, Germany

Available online: 03 Dec 2010

To cite this article: Tilmann Betsch & Andreas Glöckner (2010): Intuition in Judgment and Decision Making: Extensive Thinking
Without Effort, Psychological Inquiry, 21:4, 279-294

To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/1047840X.2010.517737

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic
reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to
anyone is expressly forbidden.

The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents
will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae, and drug doses should
be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims,
proceedings, demand, or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in
connection with or arising out of the use of this material.
Psychological Inquiry, 21: 279–294, 2010
Copyright 
C Taylor & Francis Group, LLC
ISSN: 1047-840X print / 1532-7965 online
DOI: 10.1080/1047840X.2010.517737

Intuition in Judgment and Decision Making: Extensive Thinking


Without Effort
Tilmann Betsch
Department of Psychology, University of Erfurt, Erfurt, Germany
Andreas Glöckner
Max Planck Institute for Research on Collective Goods, Bonn, Germany

We claim that intuition is capable of quickly processing multiple pieces of infor-


mation without noticeable cognitive effort. We advocate a component view stating
that intuitive processes in judgment and decision making are responsible for infor-
Downloaded by [Universitats Forschungsbiblio] at 07:00 24 November 2011

mation integration and output formation (e.g., preference, choice), whereas analytic
thinking mainly guides input formation such as search, generation, and change of
information. We present empirical evidence corroborating this notion and show that
integration of information and preference formation works without cognitive control
and is unconstrained by the amount of encoded information and cognitive capacity.
We discuss the implications of our findings for the bounded rationality perspective and
the multiple strategy approach to judgment and decision making. Finally we outline
a connectionist framework for integrating intuitive and analytic thought processes.

Seymour Epstein (2008) recently noted, “Intuition help the actor quite well to maintain a relatively high
has been given so many different meanings . . . that it level of accuracy in different choice and judgment tasks
makes one wonder whether the term has any mean- (Gigerenzer, Todd, & the ABC Research Group, 1999;
ing at all” (p. 23). Even within psychology different see also Kahneman & Klein, 2009).
concepts coexist. Intuition is conceived as a source of The heuristic approach emphasizes effort reduction
knowledge, a particular process or even a structure of and selective information processing as key features of
the brain (Winerman, 2005). The field of judgment and intuitive thought. For example, the lexicographic rule
decision making mainly resides with the process view (LEX) is a simple analytic strategy that can be used
yet proposes quite different mechanisms for the under- in decision making. It says, Do not consider all infor-
lying process (Glöckner & Witteman, 2010b; Pless- mation, rather start by comparing alternatives on the
ner, Betsch, & Betsch, 2008). Prominent approaches most important dimension. If they differ, choose the
equate intuition with heuristic processing (Gigerenzer, best and terminate further information search. There
2007; Gilovich, Griffin, & Kahneman, 2002). Accord- is ample evidence, both anecdotal and empirical, that
ing to this notion, individuals often make judgments people can successfully employ such a strategy of re-
and decisions by applying simple rules for information duced information search.
search and/or output-formation. These heuristics are In this article we advocate a markedly different
assumed to rely on only a subset of available informa- view on intuition. Note that we do not wish to dis-
tion (sometimes even only one piece). For example, cuss the usefulness of the heuristic approach. We do not
people might base probability judgments mainly on deny that individuals may apply processes described by
the representativeness of an object for a certain cate- these heuristics, especially those that apply to search.
gory (representativeness heuristic: Tversky & Kahne- We doubt, however, whether heuristics really cover the
man, 1974), or when deciding between two objects, potentials of intuitive thought. Many of the heuristics
they might choose the one that they recognize over the described in the judgment and decision making (JDM)
one they do not, while ignoring all other information literature merely seem to be simplifications of analytic
(recognition heuristic: D. G. Goldstein & Gigerenzer, thought (see Betsch, 2008, for a discussion). They cope
2002). Compared to normative rules, for example, util- with cognitive limitations by leaving out effortful infor-
ity theory’s maximization principle or formal rules of mation processes, reducing the amount of information
probability theory, such heuristics substantially reduce considered or, in short, by reducing complex judgments
cognitive effort. In some situations, however, they may to simpler ones (cf. Tversky & Kahneman, 1973, p.
lead to biased judgments and decisions (Kahneman, 207). It is our conviction that there is much more to
Slovic, & Tversky, 1982). In spite of this, they often intuition than simply a reduction in task complexity.

279
BETSCH AND GLÖCKNER

Our basic claim is that intuition is capable of deal- (see Evans, 2008, for a recent review). Accordingly,
ing with complex tasks through extensive information judgments and decisions are made in either an intu-
processing without noticeable effort. itive or analytic mode. We do not see much merit in
We set out by explaining our concept of intuition in such a notion. Rather we believe that intuition and
more detail. Then we present some empirical evidence analysis share labor by performing different types of
substantiating our point of view. Finally, we discuss the processes. We propose that intuitive processes handle
limitations of intuitive thought as well as implications output formation, that is, they are responsible for inte-
for bounded rationality and the multiple strategy ap- grating input information and producing a judgmental
proach in JDM. We close with a sketch of an integrative or choice tendency (e.g., a preference). In turn, an-
model and suggestions for future research. alytic processes are responsible for input formation,
involving controlled search, generation and temporary
change of information, which are only activated if nec-
The Nature of Intuition essary. We return to this component view later in the
article.
Processes of thinking are often sorted into two
distinct categories. These categories have been given
Downloaded by [Universitats Forschungsbiblio] at 07:00 24 November 2011

many different names (see Chaiken & Trope, 1999;


How Intuition Works: An Example From
Evans, 2008; Plessner, Betsch, & Betsch, 2008, for
Outside JDM
overviews). Henceforth we call them intuitive and an-
alytic, but we do not overly comply with any specific According to our view, intuitive processes are char-
label; more important is how we define them. In the fol- acterized by extensive thinking without effort. This
lowing we present a sketch of intuition that is rooted notion is in opposition to mainstream views on intu-
in our theoretical approach to judgment and decision ition in the field of JDM. Cautiously speaking, such a
making (Betsch, 2005; Betsch, Plessner, Schwieren, & notion may seem unrealistic from the viewpoint of a
Gütig, 2001; Glöckner & Betsch, 2008a, 2008b). decision researcher raised in the tradition of bounded
Intuitive processes operate autonomously and au- rationality. Those who point to the powers of the un-
tomatically, that is, they function without conscious conscious in decision making (e.g., Dijksterhuis, 2004;
control and cannot easily be accessed by introspec- Dijksterhuis, Bos, Nordgren, & van Baaren, 2006) en-
tion. Moreover, they can process multiple pieces of in- ter a field of harsh debate (e.g., Acker, 2008; Gonzalez-
formation in parallel. Analytic processes, in contrast, Vallejo, Lassiter, Belleza, & Lindberg, 2008). In other
are performed step-by-step. The sequence and direc- areas of cognition, however, it is quite common to
tion of these processes can be deliberatively controlled, assume that extensive processing of information can
and the actor is consciously aware of performing these easily be performed by the human mind. For exam-
processes. This definition overlaps conceptually with a ple, in speech comprehension and production as well
number of other well known definitions in the literature as pattern recognition and categorization, individuals
(e.g., see Betsch, 2008; Glöckner & Witteman, 2010, are found to be capable of rapidly processing multiple
for discussions). pieces of information in an astoundingly narrow time
We assume that intuitive processes have the follow- frame.
ing main characteristics. First, in contrast to processes Consider, for instance, the case of understanding
of deliberative construction and control (Glöckner & irony and sarcasm. Like other figures of humorous
Betsch, 2008a), intuitive processes are only marginally speech, the meaning of an ironic or sarcastic statement
constrained by cognitive capacity. Second, intuitive diverges from its surface meaning. In his famous tale
processes use all pieces of information that are mo- “A Child’s Christmas in Wales,” Dylan Thomas (1968)
mentarily activated from memory and salient in the described the following incident he experienced as a
environment (Betsch, 2005). As such, intuition pro- boy in his neighbor’s home: “Something was burning
cesses encoded information in an extensive fashion ir- all right; perhaps it was Mr Prothero. . . . But he was
respective of its origin (memory or environment). An standing in the middle of the room, saying, ‘A fine
important implication of this notion is that intuition Christmas!”’ (p. 6)
relies heavily on prior experience. The stronger prior Understanding the latter statement properly requires
experience has been consolidated in memory, the more the recipient to decide that the literal meaning of the
likely it will be activated by situational cues and, hence, sentence is not suitable to understand the intended
feed input to intuition (Betsch, 2008). This is not to meaning. This task involves complex processes such
say that intuitive processes can only operate on prior as encoding of the literal meaning, recognition and
knowledge, but prior knowledge will always be used if categorization of the context, and detection of incon-
it is activated. gruence between utterance and context. Nevertheless,
Some (but not all) dual process models in cogni- individuals rapidly grasp the meaning of statements
tion entertain an either–or view of mode application like the one in this example.
280
INTUITION IN DECISION MAKING

Research on the understanding of irony in speech Extensive and Uncontrolled Integration of


is evidencing that adult recipients simultaneously uti- Information in Judgment
lize even more stimuli such as prosodic-, mimic-,
and gesture-related information (see Gibbs & Colston, The experiments reviewed in this section show that
2007, for overviews). Nevertheless, comprehension is extensive information integration can occur even if
a very quick process in natural settings and can be per- cognitive capacities are constrained by another task
formed in less than 600 to 800 ms (e.g., Schwoebel, and the individual does not intend to form a summary
Dews, Winner, & Srinivas, 2000). Remarkebly, in- evaluation of the target objects. In the experimental set-
creasing the amount of information (e.g., by providing ting described next, participants were asked unexpect-
contextual cues) can result in a faster detection of irony edly to evaluate shares. Prior to evaluation, they had
(Amenta & Balconi, 2008). This finding is attributed to encoded outcome information about these shares in a
parallel processing. Wang, Lee, Sigman, and Dapretto dual-task setting. As a distracting task (framed as the
(2006) compared accuracy and speed in identification primary one), participants were asked to memorize the
of irony in average and clinical patients. In the latter, content of videotaped ads. Participants were told that
the ability of parallel activation of brain regions was the (ostensible) goal of the study was to assess memory
impaired. Whereas average participants showed simul- performance under distracting conditions. In line with
Downloaded by [Universitats Forschungsbiblio] at 07:00 24 November 2011

taneous activation of different brain regions and were this cover story, reading outcome information about
very quick to understand irony, the clinical patients the shares was framed as a secondary task. Specifi-
had to engage in time-consuming deliberative thought cally, they were asked to read aloud information about
to grasp the ironic intention behind the message. These shares scrolling across the bottom of the screen. Out-
and other findings led researchers to postulate that es- comes were return values produced by fictitious shares
sential parts of speech comprehension are driven by at the stock market over a period of several trading days
holistic processes operating automatically and in par- (see Figure 1). A single return value (e.g., 32) repre-
allel (e.g., Long & Graesser, 1988). sented the gain in Euro cent achieved by a particular
We have chosen this example because speech com- share (e.g., “Pittler”) on a particular trading day. Return
prehension and decision making share some important values were shown at a quick pace. Participants were
properties. In both domains, the individual must cope asked to read all appearing return values and names
with uncertainty and utilize probabilistic cues to judge of shares aloud to ensure encoding. They viewed up
a distal criterion (speech: intended meaning; decision to 140 pieces of return values produced by up to eight
situation: future benefits of behavior). Speech and ra- different shares on 20 trading days. The presentation
tional decisions are usually seen as manifestations of lasted up to 10 min. In sum, this procedure established
cognitive capabilities that are genuinely human. Regu- a high level of information overload, constrained delib-
larly, we do not expect animals to understand irony or erate processing resources with a dual task procedure,
engage in anticipative waging of outcomes. Both do- and obscured the true intention of the study. Exten-
mains involve conscious processes. In a standard com- sive pretesting showed that this procedure effectively
munication situation, the recipient focuses her atten- prevented participants from consciously integrating re-
tion on the sender. Listening itself involves conscious turn values and forming deliberate judgments of the
awareness of the situation and the content of the mes- shares.
sage. Similarly, in standard settings used in decision The distribution of return values was manipulated as
research (e.g., the gambling paradigm), the individual a within-subjects factor. Specifically, the sum, average,
intends to make a decision, focuses on the information frequency, and dispersion of return values were varied.
given, and is consciously aware of alternatives as well In line with the cover story, participants were asked to
as their respective pros and cons. recall information about the ads after the presentation.
It is our conviction that judgment and decision pro- Subsequently, however, they were unexpectedly asked
cesses capitalize on the same potentials of the brain to spontaneously evaluate each share by adjusting a
as speech comprehension processes do. According to scroll bar representing an affective scale with endpoints
our view, intuitive processes are devoted to informa- labelled good and bad.
tion integration and the formation of judgmental or Postexperimental interviews showed that partici-
choice tendencies. These processes will immediately pants indeed did not expect to evaluate the shares. Par-
be instantiated upon activation or encoding of the in- ticipants consistently reported that they had focused
formation. They work in the background while analytic their attention on the ads and did not attempt to form
processes can set in to control or change further infor- evaluations of the shares. Moreover, a recall test fol-
mation search. In the following sections, we substan- lowing the judgments showed that participants were
tiate our claim with empirical evidence. Specifically, unable to reliably reproduce characteristics of the dis-
we show that extensive information processing without tributions of the return values.
conscious control also guides judgment and decision One key research question was whether return dis-
making. tributions covaried with evaluations in a systematic
281
BETSCH AND GLÖCKNER
Downloaded by [Universitats Forschungsbiblio] at 07:00 24 November 2011

Figure 1. Screenshot of stimulus presentation used in studies on integration of


information without intention. Note. Attention-grabbing ads are shown in the
background. Return values of shares are shown in the running caption at the
bottom.

fashion. If information integration occurred automati- erage of return values produced by each of the shares.
cally during the encoding of return values, spontaneous In contrast to their spontaneous evaluative judgments,
judgments of the shares should systematically reveal participants were unable to deliberatively reconstruct
influences of the properties of the given information. sums and averages of the return distributions.
Across a number of studies, the astounding finding The results indicate that mere encoding of value
was that evaluative judgments consistently reflected the laden information (monetary outcomes) was a suffi-
sum of return values. Figure 2 shows the results of the cient condition for instigating the integration of this
first experiment from this line of research (Betsch et input information. Integration seemed to function with-
al., 2001, Exp.1). Participants were presented with five out intention and deliberate control under conditions
target shares, each appearing with the same frequency. of information overload (dual task situation) and while
The sum of their return values, however, differed be- participants’ attention was focused on another task
tween 300 and 700 Euro cents. Evaluative judgments (memorizing details of ads).
perfectly reproduced the actual variation of the sum of A series of subsequent studies further substantiated
values. Accordingly, the 300-share was rated least posi- the validity of these conclusions und ruled out alter-
tively, whereas the 700-share received the most positive native explanations of the results. For instance, we
rating. At the end of this study, participants were also showed that the results could not be explained in terms
asked to think carefully and rehearse the sum and av- of simple heuristics such as numerosity, peak-and-end

Figure 2. Results from Betsch, Plessner, Schwieren, and Gütig (2001, Exp.1).
Note. Evaluative judgments of five target shares differing with regard to sum
of return values. Higher values indicate a more intense liking.

282
INTUITION IN DECISION MAKING

(Betsch et al., 2001), familiarity and ease of recogni- Payne, Schkade, & Bettman, 1986). The Mouselab
tion (Betsch, Hoffmann, Hoffrage, & Plessner, 2003). presents information in a covered Option × Attribute
Moreover, Plessner, Betsch, Schallies, and Schwieren matrix. Individuals use the computer mouse to un-
(2008) demonstrated that the findings could be repli- cover information hidden in the fields, during which
cated in nonmonetary domains (e.g., political judgment the computer program protocols search behavior, de-
and voting behavior). cision times, and choices. The introduction of the
Of interest, the efficiency of extensive integration Mouselab was a significant advance in process trac-
was impaired if participants attempted to control the ing research. With help of this tool, decision strategies
process by deliberation. Intention and deliberation were identified on the basis of search behavior (e.g.,
changed the pattern of results systematically. In con- Payne, Bettman, & Johnson, 1988). In Mouselab ex-
trast to intuitive integration, analytic inspection of the periments it has been consistently observed that, under
given information decreased the amount of information severe task constraints (e.g., time pressure), individuals
considered (Betsch et al., 2001, Exp. 3) and caused par- change from complex to simple strategies that consider
ticipants to consider other aspects such as the size of only subsets of information. These and correspond-
information sample as weighting factors. Specifically, ing results were interpreted as strong corroborations
the given information was weighted by the size of the of the key assumptions of the bounded rationality ap-
Downloaded by [Universitats Forschungsbiblio] at 07:00 24 November 2011

sample (Betsch, Kaufmann, Lindow, Plessner, & Hoff- proach and its offspring the multiple strategy approach
mann, 2006) and its reliability (Kaufmann & Betsch, to judgment and decision making (e.g., Gigerenzer,
2009). The latter results show that analysis can change 2004; Gigerenzer & Selten, 2001; Payne, Bettman, &
the weighting of information in a fashion distinct to Johnson, 1993).
intuitive processing. We return to this issue later in the The Mouselab, however, places constraints on infor-
article when we discuss our connectionist model. mation acquisition. It requires motor behavior (mouse
Altogether, this brief review of studies provides ev- movements) to uncover information hidden in the ma-
idence in support of the notion that information in- trix. Moreover, if only one box can be open at a time
tegration can be extensive and effortless at the same and closes after another is opened, the tool places con-
time. The underlying mental processes operate au- straints on working memory, because pieces of infor-
tonomously in the background while the individual fo- mation must be remembered until the search process is
cuses on another capacity-consuming task. Integration terminated. In the Mouselab, external constraints (e.g.,
resulted in systematic preference formation. The only time pressure) enhance the costs of information acqui-
precondition for instantiating extensive accounting of sition, making it reasonable to reduce search depth.
information was that the information was encoded, that As such, the observation of adaptive strategy change
is, fed into the processing system (cf. Betsch, Plessner, shows that the costs of information search and retention
& Schallies, 2004, for a discussion). in working memory are indeed boundaries to informa-
Altogether, the results corroborate our claim that tion acquisition. This finding does not provide conclu-
intuitive processes are characterized by autonomous sive evidence, however, for the notion that information
(uncontrolled, unintentional) operation and extensive integration and calculation capacities are constrained
consideration of information. Thus far we have con- by external factors.
sidered judgments and not decisions. Moreover, the In a series of studies (Glöckner & Betsch, 2008b),
experimental setting was designed in such a way that we compared information consideration and integra-
analytic processes were directed to another task. Re- tion under time constraints in hidden and open versions
call, however, that we claimed that intuitive and an- of the information board tool (Figure 3). In one con-
alytic processes regularly interact in decision making dition we used the standard version of the Mouselab.
(but are devoted to different types of processes). In Accordingly, participants were presented with a hidden
the next sections, we present results from studies on information board so that they could access values in
choice among options using a standard paradigm from the matrix only serially by using the computer mouse.
decision research. We show that extensive integration In another condition, we employed an open informa-
of information will also occur in deliberate decision tion board. All entries to the matrix were shown on
making. In the experiments reviewed next, individu- the screen so that motor behavior was not necessary
als use and integrate all available information within a to access information and the entire stimuli set could
remarkably narrow time frame when encoding is easy. be inspected directly and easily. In all conditions, the
columns of the matrix contained three options repre-
senting different food producers. The rows contained
Extensive and Effortless Integration of binary predictions from three testers concerning the
Information in Decision Making quality of products (values) represented by the symbols
+ (good) and – (bad). The probability of being cor-
One of the most widely used tools for process trac- rect (cue validity) differed between the testers. Their
ing in deliberate decisions is the Mouselab (Johnson, cue validities ranged between .60 and .95 and were
283
BETSCH AND GLÖCKNER

Figure 3. Information board with hidden and open cells used in the studies by Glöckner and Betsch (2008b).

randomly assigned to the position of the testers (cues) out considerable mental effort. Of interest, these pro-
in the matrix. The choice task was to select the best cesses seem to operate in the background of conscious
Downloaded by [Universitats Forschungsbiblio] at 07:00 24 November 2011

producer by clicking on the option’s number with the thought, because all participants deliberatively dealt
computer mouse. with the decision problems.
We varied the patterns of values systematically to In the next section, we stretch our argument to an
allow for a choice-based measure of strategy identi- extreme. If it is true that intuitive processes can inte-
fication (see Glöckner & Betsch, 2008b, p. 1060; for grate information without considerable mental effort,
discussions of the procedure; cf. Glöckner, 2009). In processing time should be unaffected by the amount of
a first step, we assessed whether findings typically ob- information to be integrated.
served in Mouselab experiments could be replicated in
our decision domain. In line with results reported in
the literature, the majority of our participants (90%)
used lexicographic strategies when making decisions The Power of Intuition: When More
in the standard Mouselab (hidden information) under Information Is Processed Faster Than Less
time pressure. Participant choices across the different
patterns of values indicated that they considered only Before we present the study (Glöckner & Betsch,
a few pieces of information on the most important di- 2010), we need to go into more detail regarding our the-
mension (the cue with the highest validity) and ignored oretical framework for modelling intuition. Further, we
the others. Therefore, they seem to rely on only a subset also outline a connectionist model of information in-
of the given information. tegration. According to this model, intuitive processes
The pattern of results dramatically changed when consider all information contained in a working net-
information was presented in an open information work in parallel. They attempt to find a solution (e.g.,
board. Even in a very narrow time frame (less than 1.5 a preference) that coheres to constraints imposed by
s), more than 70% of participants’ choices reflected the entire pattern of information, especially their rela-
an extensive consideration and integration of informa- tions among each other. In line with this reasoning, we
tion. Specifically, their choices indicated that all cue propose that intuitive processes have another important
validities and all cue values were integrated in line with characteristic. They are sensitive to the holistic aspect
a weighted summation model. In a further study, we of the information sample, namely, the coherence in
instructed participants to make their decision by de- the pattern (note that this assumption dovetails with
liberatively integrating information according to such Gestalt theory).
a weighted additive rule. It took these participants al- In coherent patterns, judgments and decisions are
most 20 s on average to perform the task. easier to make than in incoherent patterns. For ex-
The results add to the existing evidence. They ample, if all arguments favor one option and speak
demonstrate that integration of information can hap- against another, the choice is easy. However, if pros
pen in an extensive fashion. Most important, inte- and cons are associated with both options, the choice
gration is performed in substantially less time com- is more difficult, even if normatively one option dom-
pared to conditions in which participants were asked inates the other. There is ample evidence indicating
to deliberatively perform the same operations (weight- that the degree of coherence covaries with the time
ing and adding). Thus, we concluded that informa- needed to arrive at a judgment or decision (Glöckner
tion integration can be performed intuitively without & Betsch, 2008b; Glöckner, Betsch, & Schindler,
requiring conscious, rule-based operations of weight- in press; Glöckner & Bröder, in press; Glöckner &
ing and adding. The findings corroborate our notion Hodges, in press; Hilbig & Pohl, 2009; Hochman, Ayal,
that intuitive processes can integrate information with- & Glöckner, 2010). Taking this evidence into account,

284
INTUITION IN DECISION MAKING

Table 1. Decision Tasks Used by Glöckner and Betsch supporting information was removed). We instructed
(2010). participants to make decisions as quickly as possible
Cue Patterns
and measured decision time as the main dependent
variable.
1 2 3 4 How should these manipulations affect decision
time? First, a null effect might occur if participants tend
v A B A B A B A B to use a simple search strategy such as LEX (i.e., focus
Regular: Complete decision tasks
only on the most valid cue) in reaction to the speed
0.80 + – + – + – + – instruction. Accordingly, reaction times should not be
0.70 + – + – – + – – affected by variations of amount and coherence of in-
0.60 + – – + + – + – formation because the most valid cues always differed
0.55 – + – + – + – + between options. Consequently, such a simple strategy
Reduced I: Decrease in coherence
0.80 + – + – + – + –
would relieve individuals from considering informa-
0.70 + – – + – – tion on the other cues. Second, if individuals applied
0.60 – + a more complex strategy, a main effect for amount of
0.55 – + – + – + – + information could occur. This prediction follows from
Downloaded by [Universitats Forschungsbiblio] at 07:00 24 November 2011

Reduced II: Increase in coherence multiple strategy models, which assume that process-
0.80 + – + – + – + –
0.70 + – + – – –
ing of more information consumes more cognitive re-
0.60 + – + – + – sources. Accordingly, decisions should take longer if
0.55 – + – + participants must weight eight pieces of values with
the corresponding cue validity compared to six values.
Note. A, B = options; v = cue validity.
Third, according to our prediction, an interaction ef-
fect should occur. Specifically, reaction times should
we predict that decision time should vary as function decrease with increasing information if coherence in-
of coherence but not as a function of the amount of creases as well. Conversely, reaction times should in-
information. Specifically, if additional information in- crease with increasing information if this entails a de-
creases coherence of the entire pattern, than decision crease in coherence.
time should decrease (despite the fact that there is Indeed, we found the predicted interaction effect: A
more information to be processed). Conversely, if ad- reduction of the amount of information resulted in an
ditional information decreases overall coherence, then increase in decision time when coherence decreased.
decision time should increase (despite the fact that When the reduction of information was accompanied
there is less information to be processed). We tested by a decrease of coherence, less information was pro-
this hypothesized interaction effect in the following cessed more slowly than in the control condition con-
task. taining the entire set of information. Thus, the findings
We used an open information board similar to the support our prediction that more information can be
one just introduced, with four cues of different validity processed more quickly than less information.
(55–80%) and two options (Glöckner & Betsch, 2010). The reported study provides further evidence for
The most valid cue always differentiated between the the advocated notion of intuition. Information inte-
two options. Accordingly, a consistent application of gration and preference formation seem to be largely
a simple lexicographic strategy would result in con- unaffected by the amount of encoded information and
stant decision time on average. Moreover, one option cognitive capacity. This conclusion seems to be in op-
was always better than the other with regard to their position to the dominant view in JDM research, hold-
weighted-additive value. As in the previous studies, we ing that capacity constraints require decision makers to
used different value patterns within subjects in order use simple strategies for judgment and choice. In the
to allow for choice-based identification of strategies remainder of this article, we present some suggestion
(see Table 1). As another within-subjects factor, we on the conceptual and theoretical level to solve this
varied the amount and coherence of the given informa- puzzle. We begin by reconsidering the fundaments of
tion pattern. In the control tasks, participants received simple strategies (heuristics), the bounded rationality
the entire set of eight values with a moderate level approach.
of coherence. In two other conditions, two pieces of
information (values on the least valid cue) were re- The Notion of Cognitive Effort in the
moved from the matrix (reduction of amount of in- Bounded-Rationality Approach
formation). In one of these conditions, the reduction
increased coherence (a piece of contradicting informa- The bounded-rationality approach focuses on ana-
tion was removed), whereas in the other the reduc- lytic or deliberate processes. As A. Newell and Simon
tion resulted in an decrease in coherence (a piece of (1972) stated, “We are observing intentionally rational

285
BETSCH AND GLÖCKNER

behavior” (p. 55). This focus of research is deeply curacy even under processing constraints (e.g., time
rooted in Western philosophy and Christian religion. pressure, fatigue, distraction). Most notably, however,
In accordance with the Cartesian view, decision mak- these strategies are shortcuts to deliberation. The idea
ing has been considered one of the supreme disciplines of cognitive effort is still central and undisputed sim-
of conscious thought. Even believing in God was con- ply because other processes are rarely considered at
ceived as an act of rational choice (see Blaise Pascal’s the level of specific strategies (although they are some-
“wager”). The maximization principle of utility theory times considered on a higher level of strategy selection,
pushes to the extreme the notion that decisions require e.g., Payne et al., 1993).
(intense) deliberation. According to the notion that human judgment and
Simon doubted, however, whether the maximiza- decision making is constrained by cognitive capacity,
tion principle could serve as a descriptive model of one must predict that increasing the amount of infor-
human decision making. He suspected that individu- mation to be processed will result in an increase in
als must have supernatural computational powers to cognitive effort. In other words, extensive thinking is
implement this principle. He referred to utility the- only possible to the degree that cognitive resources are
ory as an “Olympic model” (H. A. Simon, 1982) and available. The empirical evidence presented in this ar-
questioned its descriptive validity: “My first empirical ticle seems to run counter to this major tenet of the
Downloaded by [Universitats Forschungsbiblio] at 07:00 24 November 2011

proposition is that there is a complete lack of evidence bounded rationality approach. We demonstrated that
that, in actual choice situations of any complexity, these individuals can integrate multiple pieces of encoded
computations can be, or are in fact, performed” (H. A. information very quickly and even under cognitive con-
Simon, 1955, p. 104). straints. On the other hand, we must acknowledge the
In developing his bounded rationality approach, Si- bulk of evidence corroborating the bounded rationality
mon suggested that individuals do not strive to make approach. It is a robust and well-replicated finding that
the best decision but rather employ simple rules or individuals can and do employ strategies that use only
strategies that allow them to achieve a satisficing level subsets of the given information, especially in situa-
of accuracy by minimizing computational or cogni- tions that constrain cognitive capacity (Dawes, 1998;
tive effort. This notion exerted a strong impact on the Gigerenzer, 2004).
field of psychological decision research. It stipulated
the rise of multiple strategy models (e.g., Beach & Solving the Puzzle of Contradicting Evidence:
Mitchell, 1978; Gigerenzer & Goldstein, 1996; Payne Three Assumptions to Start With
et al., 1993; see Betsch, Haberstroh, & Höhle, 2002,
for an overview). These models converge in assum- Our approach rests on three main assumptions. The
ing that individuals can choose among a variety of first states that intuitive and analytic processes are dis-
strategies (or heuristics) for judgment and decision tinct. They obey to markedly different cognitive princi-
making. These strategies differ with regard to effort ples and, hence, should be considered to have emergent
and accuracy. Individuals are assumed to select strate- properties. One far-fetching implication of this propo-
gies contingent upon environmental, task, and personal sition is that intuition is not a shortcut to deliberation
factors. This approach still dominates the field of judg- but something different. According to our view, most of
ment and decision making (e.g., Gigerenzer & Selten, the strategies identified in research on multiple strategy
2001). models are not intuitive strategies but rather simplifica-
One guiding research question is how individuals tion of analysis (e.g., LEX, Peak-And-End Heuristic;
make an adaptive compromise between the cognitive see Betsch, 2008, for a discussion). They circumvent
effort and the (potential) benefits of deliberation and effortful processing by reducing the amount of infor-
accuracy of a decision. Therefore, it is essential for this mation and avoiding weighting and integration proce-
approach to quantify cognitive effort (Payne, Bettman, dures. As such they are still informed by the spirit of
& Johnson, 1992, p. 112ff). A. Newell and Simon rationalism, which assumes that decision making is a
(1972) suggested that decision processes can be de- deliberate process. However, focusing on the conscious
composed into units, the so-called elementary informa- side only may lead us to neglect the fact that thinking
tion processes (EIP). Examples of EIP are “reading in- also involves genuinely different processes. These are
formation”; “comparing values”; “eliminating values”; not subject to introspection; function without cogni-
and processes of calculation such as “subtracting,” tive control; and, most important, exploit the powers
“adding,” and “multiplying.” Over the past decades, of the brain to process information automatically and
research in this domain has identified a plethora of in parallel.
decision rules or strategies that reduce the number Second, due to their different nature, intuitive and
of EIP compared to utility theory’s weighted-additive analytic processes have different potentials and suf-
rule. These strategies, such as the LEX, elimination by fer from different constraints. The “two blades of the
aspect, and equal weight, allow individuals to achieve scissor” view of the bounded rationality approach is
or sustain a moderate to high level of decision ac- an appropriate metaphor to describe the bottleneck for
286
INTUITION IN DECISION MAKING

analytic processes. Because these are performed in a form a preference (an old notion indeed, cf. Wundt,
step-by-step fashion, they consume processing time 1907; Zajonc, 1980).
and, hence, are under the governance of working mem-
ory constraints and factors of the environment that
strain cognitive resources (the two “blades”). Applying the Component Approach to
With respect to intuitive processes, however, other Understanding Thinking Under Boundaries
boundaries seem to apply. Whereas processes of infor-
mation integration and preference formation seem to One of the key assumptions of the bounded rational-
be quite immune to variations in amount of informa- ity approach and multiple strategy models states that
tion and task constraints, pattern characteristics of the strategies or heuristics are tools of adaptation. They al-
given information do matter. In our studies, the ease low individuals to maintain mastery in changing con-
and speed of information integration was bounded by texts by making satisfactory or even good compromises
coherence in the pattern of encoded information. We between the costs of thinking and desired accuracy in
also briefly mentioned another factor. If the individual judgment or choice (Beach & Mitchell, 1978; Gigeren-
attempts to control and deliberately guide these intu- zer et al., 1999; Payne et al., 1988). First, let us recon-
itive processes, their efficiency can be impaired (e.g., sider the goals the individual is assumed to pursue in
Downloaded by [Universitats Forschungsbiblio] at 07:00 24 November 2011

Betsch, Plessner, et al., 2004). Similar results can be strategy selection. The bounded rationality approach
found in the literature on human error (e.g., Reason, assumes that constraints foster application of strate-
1992). As such, the notion of boundaries is an impor- gies that reduce the number of EIPs needed to make a
tant and valid one. Acknowledging that boundaries are decision. A straight means to achieve this goal is selec-
process specific, however, we must extend our cata- tive search. Accordingly, simple strategies (e.g., LEX)
logues by those types of boundaries that apply to intu- focus on only a few important pieces of information
itive processes. (e.g., outcomes on the most important attribute or most
Third, and most important, we assume that intuition valid cue). Selective search reduces not only the num-
and analyses are component processes rather than dif- ber of EIPs needed to form the input to the choice but
ferent modes of thinking. According to this view, a also the number of EIPs needed to transform the input
judgment or decision is not made in either the intuitive to an output (e.g., a choice).
or analytic mode. Rather, intuition and analyses are as- In our component approach we assume that input
sumed to be responsible for guiding different types of and output formation is guided by genuinely different
subprocesses (components). This view converges with processes, analyses and intuition, respectively. In line
recent developments in the literature on dual process with the bounded rationality approach, we also assume
models. Granting substantial empirical evidence, Fer- that the costs for analysis covary with the number of
reira, Garcia-Marques, Sherman, and Sherman (2006) deliberate processing steps (EIPs) because these pro-
concluded that “judgment under uncertainty is neither cesses are performed step-by-step. In addition, we pos-
an automatic nor a controlled process but . . . reflects tulate that the costs for intuition do not systematically
both processes, with each making independent contri- covary with the number of processing steps, because
butions” (p. 798). they can be performed in parallel. Moreover, we pos-
We suggested that information integration and out- tulate that intuitive processes are governed by different
put formation (e.g., preference, choice) is performed types of constraints than analytic processes, such as
by intuitive processes, whereas forming the input holistic aspects of the information pattern (e.g., coher-
to integration often requires analysis. These analytic ence).
processes may involve directed search for informa- The bounded rationality approach and multiple
tion (e.g., looking for the most valid cues, asking strategy models predict commensurate effects of con-
an expert for advice), making sense of given in- straints on processing. They converge in assuming that
formation (e.g., assessing how given consequences constraining processing time or cognitive resources
affect personal goals), anticipating future events, (e.g., via load manipulation) would both bound input
making inferences to generate information, and so and output formation. For instance, severe time pres-
forth. sure should increase the likelihood that strategies are
As such, we conceive a judgment or decision as employed, which reduce the amount of information
the product of the collaboration of intuition and anal- and/or complexity of the decision rule. Because con-
yses. Whereas the depth of analysis can vary, we as- straints have commensurate effects on all steps, it is
sume that intuitive processes always work in the mental possible to allocate resources in a cost-compensating
background even if the individual deliberatively faces fashion. For instance, the individual may first attempt
a judgment or decision task (see also the notion of to search as much information as possible, but then
default-interventionist models by Evans, 2008). There- apply a very simple rule that considers only a small
fore, these intuitive processes are inevitable. Prefer- subset of the encoded information when time runs out
ences evolve even if the individual does not intend to (or vice versa).
287
BETSCH AND GLÖCKNER

In contrast, our component approach predicts or- Toward an Integrative Model of Judgment and
thogonal effects for different types of constraints. Ac- Decision Making
cordingly, distinct types of factors independently con-
strain input and output formation. Therefore, compen- The literature on judgment and decision making
sation of costs between input and output processes is hosts descriptions of a plethora of strategies and heuris-
neither possible nor necessary. Limiting processing re- tics. Each strategy is a combination of processes, con-
sources (time, capacity) will constrain only input but sisting of different rules for information search, com-
not output formation. Consequently, we predict that parison, integration, termination, and choice (so-called
only input formation will covary as a function of lim- building blocks; Gigerenzer et al., 1999). The model
ited resources. outlined in the following starts with the assumption that
One puzzling finding in the area of multiple strat- there is only one all-purpose rule for integration and
egy research is that individuals use simple strategies choice (for similar assertions of single strategy models,
(such as LEX) far less often than expected theoreti- see Lee & Cummins, 2004; B. R. Newell, 2005) but
cally. Even in environments that ideally favor the ap- that there are different rules for search, generation, and
plication of such simple strategies (e.g., time pressure change of information. In other words, we assume that
in a Mouselab decision task), there is still a substantial individuals use different strategies for input formation
Downloaded by [Universitats Forschungsbiblio] at 07:00 24 November 2011

proportion of participants integrating information in a but that they apply a general, multifunctional mecha-
complex fashion (Bröder, 2003; Glöckner & Hodges, nism for output formation. This mechanism is assumed
in press; B. R. Newell & Shanks, 2003). This finding to obey to the principles we described as the charac-
is not surprising from the viewpoint of our component teristics of intuition. It operates unintentionally and
model. Once information has been fed into the process- automatically, and it processes information in parallel.
ing system, intuition will use this sample of informa- We suggest that this mechanism can be understood and
tion irrespective of amount and capacity. Individuals formally described in terms of a connectionist model.
seem to have an intuitive understanding of the poten- This assertion, however, does not preclude that there
tials of their intuition. They do not spare their mind might also be other automatic mechanisms involved in
but often seem to get as much information as possible. decision making (see Glöckner & Witteman, 2010a,
Applying measures for strategy identification based on for a discussion).
choices, decision times, and confidence show that they Connectionist models have been applied to a vari-
regularly use and integrate the entire set of encoded in- ety of areas in cognition such as reading (McClelland
formation (e.g., Glöckner, 2009; Glöckner & Bröder, & Rumelhart, 1981), explanatory coherence (Thagard,
in press). 1989), attribution (Read & Marcus-Newhall, 1993),
What happens if we release boundaries on input stereotyping (Kunda & Thagard, 1996), and decision
formation so that information acquisition consumes making (e.g., Glöckner et al., in press; Holyoak & Si-
only minimal resources? Recall that multiple strategy mon, 1999; Thagard & Millgram, 1995). In recent arti-
models still predict that costs will increase with in- cles, we advanced a specific version of the connection-
creasing amounts of information, because integrating ist approach, the parallel-constraint-satisfaction (PCS)
involves costly EIPs as well. In our decision stud- model, to apply to multiattribute decision making
ies, we created such an easy-access situation using (Betsch, 2005; Glöckner & Betsch, 2008a). In the fol-
an open information board. Outcome information was lowing sections, we sketch the major assumptions of
binary and depicted in symbols (+, –). Only cue va- our advanced PCS model and discuss some implica-
lidities were shown as numbers. For simplicity, as- tions and empirical predictions.
sume that the costs for input formation are minimal
in this case. Thus, processing time (as an indicator
Input: The Working Network
of cognitive effort) should vary only with effort in-
vested in output formation. In contrast to this pre- The connectionist approach uses a network
diction of the multiple strategy models, we found metaphor to model how information is represented
no main effect for amount of information. Rather we in the mind (Holyoak & Spellman, 1993). Elements
found that processing time covaried with holistic pat- (nodes) and weights on the connections between the
tern characteristics. This finding nicely corroborates elements form the structure of the network. A working
the component model predicting that different fac- network represents the decision at stake. It contains fea-
tors constrain analyses and intuition in an orthogonal tures of the situation, options, goals, and outcome infor-
fashion. mation (see symbolic connectionism; Holyoak, 1991).
This brief discussion may illustrate how the It may also contain other pieces of information that
bounded rationality approach can be fruitfully ad- have been recently encoded or activated from mem-
vanced by a component view assuming that intuition ory. Connections between the elements can represent
and analysis refer to different components rather than their learned relation reflecting, for instance, covari-
to different types of strategies. ation, rates of reinforcement and punishment, logical
288
INTUITION IN DECISION MAKING

relations such as negation or causation, and so forth. There are other bottlenecks that are due to analytic
Formally, these relations are expressed by positive or thinking. We noted earlier that trying to supervise intu-
negative weights on the connections. When activation ition may decrease its effectiveness. In the experiments
is passed through the network, a positive weight causes on implicit formation of preferences (Betsch, Plessner,
activation and a negative weight causes deactivation of & Schallies, 2004, for an overview), we found that
a linked element. trying to explicitly form a preference hindered partici-
pants from reproducing their intuitively formed pattern
of preferences that so closely mirrored their actual ex-
Output: Application of the PCS Rule periences.
Recall the assumed functioning of PCS. By paral-
A decision is made by applying a PCS rule (see
lel passing of activation, the activation of elements is
Read, Vanman, & Miller, 1997, for an excellent intro-
changed to satisfy the characteristics of the entire pat-
duction). Information is passed in parallel through the
tern of interrelations among elements (the structure of
network. The activations of the elements are simultane-
weights in the network). The resulting activation of an
ously updated and constrained by the given structure
element emerges within the network as a result of an it-
of weights in the working network. By iterating this
erative updating process. Analytic thinking is a process
Downloaded by [Universitats Forschungsbiblio] at 07:00 24 November 2011

updating process, the PCS rule strives for a solution


by which the focus of attention is directed to elements
in which all elements optimally cohere with all other
of the network. In terms of connectionist modeling, the
elements taking into account the constraints in the net-
focused element receives a dramatic change in activa-
work in a parallel manner. This occurs in an iterative
tion from outside the network. These changes may help
process of updating node activations. In most simple
or hinder PCS to reach a solution. If the individual fo-
networks, activation of all nodes reaches an asymptotic
cuses pieces of information that, for instance, promote
level after a small number of iterations and the process
the dominating option, than PCS can jump toward ter-
is terminated. Activations of elements are used as the
mination. However, if the focused elements are those
basis for judgments or decisions. In the case of deci-
that need to be deactivated to achieve coherence, an-
sions, the options with the highest activation will be
alytic thinking bugs PCS. In the case of our studies,
chosen (see Betsch, 2005, for a variant of this rule). In
individuals could not systematically access relevant
the case of making a judgment about a single object
characteristics of prior outcome distributions. There-
on a certain criterion dimension, estimations reflect the
fore, attentional focus (explicitly considering certain
strength of the element’s activation.
outcomes) may have varied randomly and diluted or
even destroyed appropriate differences in the activa-
tions of the options.
Bottlenecks to the PCS Process
Because the PCS rule attempts to maximize coher-
The Algebra of Intuitive Processing
ence, the effectiveness and speed of this process is
mainly dependent on the holistic characteristics of the PCS employs a nonlinear rule for cue activation (i.e.,
information pattern but not on the number of elements. a sigmoid activation function; McClelland & Rumel-
If there is already a high level of coherence, the PCS hart, 1981). Nevertheless, simulated distributions of
rule needs only a few iterations to arrive at a solution. the output of this process converge with those pro-
Accordingly, those decisions can be made very quickly duced by a weighted summation (or weighted additive
regardless of the amount of information contained in rule; cf. Glöckner & Herbold, in press; Glöckner &
the working network. On the other hand, if initial co- Hodges, in press). The results from simulation con-
herence in the pattern is low (e.g., because there is verge with empirical findings. For judgments it has
contradicting evidence activating and deactivating op- been shown that they can be approximated well by a
tions at the same time), it will take the PCS rule more weighted linear model (see Brehmer, 1994; Hammond,
iterations to change the pattern in order to achieve Hamm, Grassia, & Pearson, 1987; Karelaia & Hoga-
coherence. On the phenomenological level, incoher- rth, 2008). We also found that evaluations reflect the
ence will manifest itself in extension of time needed to sum of all values of prior experiences with the target
make a decision. Iterations in a PCS network have been object and not only their numerosity (e.g., Betsch et al.,
proven to be a good predictor for decision times even 2001). In our decision studies with an open informa-
on an individual level (Glöckner & Bröder, in press; tion board, even decisions under time pressure showed
Glöckner & Hodges, in press). In a network structure that the pattern of choices mapped on the differences
with a high degree of contradiction and/or high desired between the alternatives in terms of their weighted
level of coherence (threshold θ ; Glöckner & Betsch, sum of values (Glöckner & Betsch, 2008a, 2008b,
2008a), PCS can fail to reach a solution of acceptable 2010). Furthermore, it should be mentioned that, in
coherence. Under such condition the network must be strong support of the PCS perspective, a coherence ef-
restructured (see next). fect, that is, a systematic reevaluation of evidence in
289
BETSCH AND GLÖCKNER

favor of the leading option in the decision process, lete. However, weights can be temporarily changed by
has been demonstrated in many kinds of decision tasks DC (whereas lasting changes might require feedback
(e.g., DeKay, Patino-Echeverri, & Fischbeck, 2009a, learning). Assume an individual consciously realizes
2009b; Glöckner et al., in press; Holyoak & Simon, that a routine behavior is inappropriate under the given
1999; Russo, Carlson, Meloy, & Yong, 2008; Russo, decision situation. This change in perceived instrumen-
Meloy, & Medvec, 1998; Russo, Medvec , & Meloy, tality can be modeled as a change of the weights on
1996; D. Simon, Krawczyk, & Holyoak, 2004; D. Si- the association between the goals and the behavior.
mon, Pham, Le, & Holyoak, 2001; D. Simon, Snow & Maintaining this change, however, requires cognitive
Read, 2004, for similar earlier theoretical approaches; control and, hence, cognitive effort. Factors that addi-
see also Montgomery, 1989; Svenson, 1992). Further- tionally consume cognitive resources reduce the like-
more, recent findings indicate that arousal does indeed lihood that changes can be maintained during a deci-
increase with decreasing coherence in decision tasks sion. The lower the capacity for deliberative control
as suggested by PCS models (Glöckner & Hochman, over the representation of the decision problem, the
in press; Hochman et al., 2010). higher the likelihood that weights will reach their prior
state. Hence, one would predict that deviation from
a decision routine under altered situational conditions
Downloaded by [Universitats Forschungsbiblio] at 07:00 24 November 2011

The Interplay of Analytic and Intuitive


requires DC processes to function effectively, a predic-
Processes
tion that is strongly corroborated by the evidence (e.g.,
PCS processes are assumed to function by default, Betsch, Fiedler, & Brinkmann, 1998; Betsch, Haber-
regardless of whether analytic processes are used ad- stroh, & Höhle, 2004). This example shows how in-
ditionally (for an overview of other recent default- tuitive and analytic processes both have their specific
interventionist models, see Evans, 2008). According to powers. Their interaction and collaboration is neces-
the component view, intuitive and analytic processes sary to promote adaptive decision making.
serve different functions. We described the interplay By now, we have considered only situations in
between these processes in detail in a previous pa- which the input (working network) allows for effective
per (Glöckner & Betsch, 2008a). We referred to ana- application and termination of PCS processes. What
lytic operations as processes of deliberate construction happens, however, if PCS fails to achieve an accept-
(DC). DC involves input formation such as active in- able level of coherence in the network (i.e., coherence
formation search, generation, and change. In our PCS is below the aspired threshold)? In our PCS model, we
model, we assumed that DC is not a necessary condi- assumed that failure to achieve coherence is an endoge-
tion for reaching a decision. Sometimes, salient infor- nous factor that instigates DC operations (Glöckner &
mation in the environment and accessible information Betsch, 2008a). We assumed that upon failure a sec-
from memory will provide an input sample of infor- ondary working network is constituted containing DC
mation that suffices to reach the necessary level of operations and strategies as options. Again, the PCS
coherence for a judgment or decision to be made. This rule is applied to this secondary network to select a DC
may be primarily the case for many routine decision operation, which is then applied to change the primary
situations that typically do not require additional infor- network representing the original decision problem.
mation search and generation. In other situations, DC Although these assumptions are not yet formally im-
will always be involved. For example, in the Mouselab plemented in the model, they provide a starting point
used in decision research, the options are unfamiliar for theoretically modeling the selection of strategies
to the participant and information is hidden in a ma- for information search and change.
trix. Under such conditions, a working network must
be actively formed prior to PCS processing. In the re-
mainder of this section we outline two examples of
how intuitive and analytic processes interact. Directions for Future Research
An important potential of DC is to change infor-
mation temporarily in an intended direction. Intuition, The majority of studies on JDM still employ writ-
on the contrary, does not have such powers. Specifi- ten descriptions of relevant information. For instance,
cally, PCS processes can change only activations, not the gambling paradigm (the “drosophila” of decision
the structure of the network. Many aspects of the net- research, cf. W. M. Goldstein & Hogarth, 1997) pro-
work stem from prior learning. For example, a strong vides individuals with stated probabilities and stated
positive weight on a relation between an option and a values. In this paradigm, encoding of information sys-
goal may reflect reinforcement history. Such weights tematically involves only one channel. Moreover, the
provide the given constraints under which PCS must individual can rely only on the (new) stimulus informa-
find a solution. If decisions were solely guided by PCS, tion from the environment and not on prior knowledge.
individuals would have difficulty instantly adapting to Conversely, in natural settings, decision information
changes in the world that render prior behavior obso- stems from multiple sources and can be simultaneously
290
INTUITION IN DECISION MAKING

encoded via multiple channels (e.g., visual, auditory, Ebersbach (2009) demonstrated that kindergarten chil-
memory). dren show remarkabe capabilities of spontaneously in-
For example, assume you visit a restaurant with tegrating three orthogonally varying stimulus dimen-
friends. The menu contains pictures of the different sions in their judgments of volume. To drive this ar-
dishes and written description of their ingredients. gument to the extreme, many studies show that even
Moreover, your friends comment on the menu, utter monkeys (Platt & Glimcher, 1999) and sticklebacks
their own preferences, and may evoke examples of their (Künzler & Bakker, 2001) make choices indicating
prior experiences. You can additionally capitalize on an integration of information in a weighted compen-
your experiences with eating similar dishes that come satory manner. Research and theorizing in the field
to your mind easily in form of cognitive and affective of judgment and decision making might benefit from
representations. In such a situation, input information acknowledging these findings.
to the decision is fed through multiple channels (oral,
visual, memory). Different types of information are
encoded simultaneously. In a relatively effortless fash- Conclusion
ion, you are provided with a rich informational base for
your decision. In these and similar situations that are According to the advocated approach to intuition,
Downloaded by [Universitats Forschungsbiblio] at 07:00 24 November 2011

encountered frequently in everyday life, intuition can not all processes of thinking are constrained by limits
reveal its powers. Integration and preference formation of computational capabilities. We suggested that in-
happens en passant. Unfortunately, multimodal situa- tuition can capitalize on the powers of autonomous,
tions are as of yet very rarely considered in decision automatic, nonintentional processes that are character-
research. The naturalistic decision-making approach ized by parallel processing. These parallel processes
must be mentioned as an exception (Klein, 1999; Klein, are much less constrained by the amount of informa-
Orasanu, Calderwood, & Zsambock, 1993). Studies in tion. Extensive consideration of multiple pieces of in-
this area are often conducted in the field yet suffer from formation can happen in an astoundingly narrow time
insufficient experimental control. Change and devel- frame. We suggested that intuitive processes are re-
opment of research tools toward multimodal stimulus sponsible for transforming a sample of input informa-
presentation is both a challenging and promising task tion into an output (judgment, choice). We claimed that
for the future. there are not two modes of thinking that can be used
The processes of intuitive thinking do not apply alternatively. Rather, we propose that intuitive and an-
only to judgment and decision making. The connec- alytic processes are components that operate together
tionist approach views these processes as fundamental to form judgment and decisions. Such a component
to many areas of cognition including, for instance, per- view can be integrated in a connectionist model to de-
ception and speech comprehension. Accordingly, one cision making. We showed that such a model helps to
should expect that extensive integration of information advance the bounded rationality approach as well as
can be performed by decision makers from an early our understanding of strategic adaptation to situational
stage on. For example, preschool children who already changes.
do well in speech comprehension should be capable of
applying the PCS rule to decisions without effort and
instruction. Unfortunately, we still know little about Note
how children make decisions. Most decision research
with children is conducted and published in the field Address correspondence to Tilmann Betsch, De-
of developmental psychology (e.g., Davidson & Hud- partment of Psychology, University of Erfurt, Nord-
son, 1988; Gao, Li, Bai, Lin, & Wei, 2009; Knight, hauser Strasse 63, D-99089 Erfurt, Germany. E-mail:
Berning, Wilson, & Chao, 1987; Schlottmann, 2001). tilmann.betsch@uni-erfurt.de
Members of the JDM community only occasionally
study child decision making (e.g., Levin, Weller, Ped-
erson & Harshman, 2007; Reyna & Ellis, 1994). We References
see much merit in extending this line of research with
a stronger focus on how children intuitively integrate Acker, F. (2008). New findings on unconscious versus conscious
thought in decision making: Additional empirical data and
information. We believe that valuable lessons about meta-analysis. Judgment and Decision Making, 3, 292–303.
intuitions and analysis can be learned in this domain Amenta, S., & Balconi, M. (2008). Understanding irony: An ERP
(cf. Jacobs & Klaczynski, 2005). The few studies that analysis on the elaboration of acoustic ironic statements. Neu-
use functional measurement in nonadult participants ropsychological Trends, 3, 7–27.
provide first evidence in favor of our notion assum- Beach, L. R., & Mitchell, T. R. (1978). A contingency model for the
selection of decision strategies. Academy Management Review,
ing that integration of multiple pieces of information 3, 439–449.
can be easily performed even from an early age (e.g., Betsch, T. (2005). Preference theory—An affect-based approach to
Ebersbach, 2009; Schlottmann, 2001). For example, recurrent decision making. In T. Betsch & S. Haberstroh (Eds.),

291
BETSCH AND GLÖCKNER

The routines of decision making (pp. 39–65). Mahwah, NJ: Epstein, S. (2008). Intuition from the perspective of cognitive-
Erlbaum. experiential self-theory. In H. Plessner, C. Betsch, & T. Betsch
Betsch, T. (2008). The nature of intuition and its neglect in research (Eds.), Intuition in judgment and decision making (pp. 23–37).
on judgment and decision making. In H. Plessner, C. Betsch, New York, NY: Erlbaum.
& T. Betsch (Eds.), Intuition in judgment and decision making Evans, J. S. B. T. (2008). Dual-processing accounts of reasoning,
(pp. 3–22). New York, NY: Erlbaum. judgment, and social cognition. Annual Review of Psychology,
Betsch, T., Fiedler, K., & Brinkmann, B. J. (1998). Behavioral rou- 59, 255–278.
tines in decision making: The effects of novelty in task presen- Ferreira, M. B., Garcia-Marques, L., Sherman, S. J., & Sherman,
tation and time pressure on routine maintenance and deviation. J. W. (2006). Automatic and controlled components of judg-
European Journal of Social Psychology, 28, 861–878. ment and decision making. Journal of Personality and Social
Betsch, T., Haberstroh, S., & Höhle, C. (2002). Explaining routinized Psychology, 91, 797–813.
decision making—A review of theories and models. Theory and Gao, G., Li, H., Bai, J., Lin, C., & Wei, Y. (2009). Young children’s
Psychology, 12, 453–488. affective decision-making in a gambling task: Does difficulty in
Betsch, T., Haberstroh, S., Molter, B., & Glöckner, A. (2004). Oops, learning the gain/loss schedule matter? Cognitive Development,
I did it again—Relapse errors in routinized decision making. 24, 183–191.
Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 93, Gibbs, R. W., & Colston, H. L. (Eds.). (2007). Irony in language and
62–74. thought: A cognitive science reader. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Betsch, T., Hoffmann, K., Hoffrage, U., & Plessner, H. (2003). In- Gigerenzer, G. (2004). Fast and frugal heuristics: The tools of
Downloaded by [Universitats Forschungsbiblio] at 07:00 24 November 2011

tuition beyond recognition: When less familiar events are liked bounded rationality. In D. Koehler & N. Harvey (Eds.), Hand-
more. Experimental Psychology, 50, 49–54. book of judgment and decision making (pp. 62–88). Oxford,
Betsch, T., Kaufmann, M., Lindow, F., Plessner, H., & Hoffmann, UK: Blackwell.
K. (2006). Different principles of information aggregation in Gigerenzer, G. (2007). Gut feelings. The intelligence of the uncon-
implicit and explicit attitude formation. European Journal of scious. New York: Viking.
Social Psychology, 36, 887–905. Gigerenzer, G., & Goldstein, D. G. (1996). Reasoning the fast and
Betsch, T., Plessner, H., & Schallies, E. (2004). The value-account frugal way: Models of bounded rationality. Psychological Re-
model of attitude formation. In G. R. Maio & G. Haddock view, 103, 650–669.
(Eds.), Contemporary perspectives on the psychology of atti- Gigerenzer, G., & Selten, R. (Eds.). (2001). Bounded rationality—
tudes (pp. 251–273). Hove, UK: Psychology Press. The adaptive toolbox. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Betsch, T., Plessner, H., & Schallies, E. (2004). The value-account Gigerenzer, G., Todd, P. M., and the ABC Research Group (1999).
model of attitude formation. In G. R. Maio & G. Haddock (eds.), Simple heuristics that make us smart. Oxford, UK: Oxford
Contemporary perspectives on the psychology of attitudes (pp. University Press.
251–273). London, UK: Psychology Press. Gilovich, T., Griffin, D., & Kahneman, D. (Eds.). (2002). Heuristics
Betsch, T., Plessner, H., Schwieren, C., & Gütig, R. (2001). I like and biases: The psychology of intuitive judgment. Cambridge,
it but I don’t know why: A value-account approach to implicit UK: Cambridge University Press.
attitude formation. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, Glöckner, A. (2009). Investigating intuitive and deliberate processes
27, 242–253. statistically: The Multiple-Measure Maximum Likelihood strat-
Brehmer, B. (1994). The psychology of linear judgement models. egy classification method. Judgment and Decision Making, 4,
Acta Psychologica, 87, 137–154. 186–199.
Bröder, A. (2003). Decision making with the “adaptive toolbox”: Glöckner, A., & Betsch, T. (2008a). Modelling option and strategy
Influence of environmental structure, intelligence, and working choices with connectionist networks: Towards an integrative
memory load. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, model of automatic and deliberate decision making. Judgment
Memory, and Cognition, 29, 611–625. and Decision Making, 3, 215–228.
Chaiken, S., & Trope, Y. (Eds.), (1999). Dual-process theories in Glöckner, A., & Betsch, T. (2008b). Multiple-reason decision mak-
social psychology. New York, NY: Guilford. ing based on automatic processing. Journal of Experimental
Davidson, D., & Hudson, J. (1988). The effects of decision reversibil- Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition, 34, 1055–1075.
ity and decision importance on children’s decision making. Glöckner, A., & Betsch, T. (2010). Decisions beyond bound-
Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 46, 35–40. aries: When more information is processed faster than less.
Dawes, R. M. (1998). Behavioral decision making and judgment. In Manuscript submitted for publication.
D. T. Gilbert, S. T. Fiske, & G. Lindzey (Eds.), The handbook Glöckner, A., Betsch, T., & Schindler, N. (in press). Construction
of social psychology—Fourth edition (Vol. 1, pp. 497–548). of probabilistic inferences by constraint satisfaction. Journal of
Boston: McGraw-Hill. Behavioral Decision Making.
DeKay, M. L., Patino-Echeverri, D., & Fischbeck, P. S. (2009a). Glöckner, A., & Bröder, A. (in press). Processing of recognition
Better safe than sorry: precautionary reasoning and implied information and additional cues: A model-based analysis of
dominance in risky decisions. Journal of Behavioral Decision choice, confidence, and response time. Judgment and Decision
Making, 22, 338–361. Making.
DeKay, M. L., Patino-Echeverri, D., & Fischbeck, P. S. (2009b). Glöckner, A., & Herbold, A.-K. (in press). An eye-tracking study on
Distortion of probability and outcome information in risky de- information processing in risky decisions: Evidence for com-
cisions. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Pro- pensatory strategies based on automatic processes. Journal of
cesses, 109, 79–92. Behavioral Decision Making.
Dijksterhuis, A. (2004). Think different: The merits of unconscious Glöckner, A., & Hochman, G. (in press). The interplay of experience-
though in preference development and decision making. Jour- based affective and probabilistic cues in decision making:
nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 87, 586–598. Arousal increases when experience and additional cues con-
Dijksterhuis, A., Bos, M. W., Nordgren, L. F., & van Baaren, R. B. flict. Experimental Psychology.
(2006). On making the right choice: The deliberation-without- Glöckner, A., & Hodges, S. D. (in press). Parallel constraint satis-
attention effect. Science, 311, 1005–1007. faction in memory-based decisions. Experimental Psychology.
Ebersbach, M. (2009). Achieving a new dimension: Children inte- Glöckner, A., & Witteman, C. L. M. (2010a). Beyond dual-process
grate three stimulus dimensions in volume estimations. Devel- models: A categorization of processes underlying intuitive judg-
opmental Psychology, 45, 877–883. ment and decision making. Thinking & Reasoning, 16, 1–25.

292
INTUITION IN DECISION MAKING

Glöckner, A., & Witteman, C. L. M. (Eds.). (2010b). Foundations Kunda, Z., & Thagard, P. (1996). Forming impressions from stereo-
for tracing intuition: Challenges and methods. London: Psy- types, traits, and behaviors: A parallel-constraint-satisfaction
chology Press. theory. Psychological Review, 103, 284–208.
Goldstein, D. G., & Gigerenzer, G. (2002). Models of ecological Lee, M. D., & Cummins, T. D. R. (2004). Evidence accumulation in
rationality: The recognition heuristic. Psychological Review, decision making: Unifying the “take the best” and the “rational”
109, 75–90. models. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 11, 343–352.
Goldstein, W. M., & Hogarth, R. M. (1997). Judgment and de- Levin, I. P., Weller, J. A., Pederson, A. A., & Harshman, L. A.
cision research: Some historical context. In W. M. Goldstein (2007). Age-related differences in adaptive decision making:
& R. M. Hogarth (Ed.), Research on judgment and decision Sensitivity to expected value in risky choice. Judgment and
making: Currents, connections and controversies (pp. 3–65). Decision Making, 2, 225–233.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Long, D. L., & Graesser, A. C. (1988). Wit and humour in discourse
Gonzalez-Vallejo, C., Lassiter, G. D., Belleza, F., & Lindberg, M. processes. Discourse Process, 11, 35–60.
J. (2008). “Save angels perhaps”: A critical examination of McClelland, J. L., & Rumelhart, D. E. (1981). An interactive activa-
Unconscious Thought Theory and the Deliberation-Without tion model of context effects in letter perception: I. An account
Intention Effect. Review of General Psychology, 12, 282– of basic findings. Psychological Review, 88, 375–407.
296. Montgomery, H. (1989). From cognition to action: The search for
Hammond, K. R., Hamm, R. M., Grassia, J., & Pearson, T. (1987). dominance in decision making. In H. Montgomery & O. Sven-
Direct comparison of the efficacy of intuitive judgment and son (Eds.), Process and structure in human decision making
Downloaded by [Universitats Forschungsbiblio] at 07:00 24 November 2011

analytical cognition in expert judgment. IEEE Transactions on (pp. 23–49). Oxford, UK: Wiley & Sons.
Systems, Man, and Cybernetics, 17, 753–770. Newell, A., & Simon, H. A. (1972). Human problem solving. Engle-
Hilbig, B. E., & Pohl, R. F. (2009). Ignorance- versus evidence- wood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
based decision making: A decision time analysis of the recogni- Newell, B. R. (2005). Re-visions of rationality? Trends in Cognitive
tion heuristic. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Sciences, 9, 11–15.
Memory, and Cognition, 35, 1296–1305. Newell, B. R., & Shanks, D. R. (2003). Take the best or look at
Hochman, G., Ayal, S., & Glöckner, A. (2010). Physiological arousal the rest? Factors influencing “one-reason” decision making.
in processing recognition information: Ignoring or integrat- Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and
ing cognitive cues? Judgment and Decision Making, 5, 285– Cognition, 29, 53–65.
299. Payne, J. W., Bettman, J. R., & Johnson, E. J. (1988). Adaptive
Holyoak, K. J. (1991). Symbolic connectionism: Toward third- strategy selection in decision making. Journal of Experimental
generation theories of expertise. In K. A. Ericsson & J. Smith Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition, 14, 534–552.
(Eds.), Toward a general theory of expertise (pp. 301–336). Payne, J. W., Bettman, J. R., & Johnson, E. J. (1992). Behavioral de-
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. cision research: A constructive processing perspective. Annual
Holyoak, K. J., & Simon, D. (1999). Bidirectional reasoning in deci- Review of Psychology, 43, 87–131.
sion making by constraint satisfaction. Journal of Experimental Payne, J. W., Bettman, J. R., & Johnson, E. J. (1993). The adaptive
Psychology: General, 128(1), 3–31. decision maker. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Holyoak, K. J., & Spellman, B. A. (1993). Thinking. Annual Review Platt, M. L., & Glimcher, P. W. (1999). Neural correlates of decision
of Psychology, 44, 265–315. variables in parietal cortex. Nature, 400, 233–238.
Jacobs, J. E., & Klaczynski, P. A. (Eds.). (2005). The development Plessner, H., Betsch, C., &.Betsch, T. (Eds.). (2008). Intuition in
of judgement and decision making in children and adolescents. judgment and decision making. New York, NY: Erlbaum.
Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Plessner, H., Betsch, T., Schallies, E., & Schwieren, C. (2008). Auto-
Johnson, E. J., Payne, J. W., Schkade, D. A., & Bettman, J. R. matic online formation of implicit attitudes towards politicians
(1986). Monitoring information processing and decisions: The as a basis for intuitive voting behaviour. In H. Plessner, C.
mouselab system. Unpublished manuscript, Center for Decision Betsch, &T. Betsch (Eds.), Intuition in judgment and decision
Studies, Fuqua School of Business, Duke University, Durham, Making (pp. 107–117). New York, NY: Erlbaum.
NC. Read, S. J., & Marcus-Newhall, A. (1993). Explanatory coherence in
Kahneman, D., & Klein, G. (2009). Conditions for intuitive exper- social explanations: A parallel distributed processing account.
tise: A failure to disagree. American Psychologist, 64, 515–526. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 65, 429–447.
Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., & Tversky, A. (Eds.). (1982). Judgment un- Read, S. J., Vanman, E. J., & Miller, L. C. (1997). Connectionism,
der uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Cambridge, UK: Cam- parallel constraint satisfaction, and Gestalt principles: (Re) In-
bridge University Press. troducing cognitive dynamics to social psychology. Personality
Karelaia, N., & Hogarth, R. M. (2008). Determinants of linear judg- and Social Psychology Review, 1, 26–53.
ment: A meta-analysis of lens model studies. Psychological Reason, J. (1992). Human error. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Uni-
Bulletin, 134, 404–426. versity Press.
Kaufmann, M., & Betsch, T. (2009). Origins of the sample-size effect Reyna, V. F., & Ellis, S. C. (1994). Fuzzy-trace theory and fram-
in explicit evaluative judgments. Experimental Psychology, 56, ing e?ects in children’s risky decision making. Psychological
344–353. Science, 5, 275–279.
Klein, G. (1999). Sources of power. How people make decisions. Russo, J. E., Carlson, K. A., Meloy, M. G., & Yong, K. (2008). The
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. goal of consistency as a cause of information distortion. Journal
Klein, G., Orasanu, J., Calderwood, R., & Zsambock, C. E. (1993). of Experimental Psychology: General, 137, 456–470.
Decision making in action: models and methods. Norwood, NJ: Russo, J., Medvec, V., & Meloy, M. (1996). The distortion of infor-
Ablex. mation during decisions. Organizational Behavior and Human
Knight, G. P., Berning, A. L., Wilson, S. L., & Chao, C.-C. (1987). Decision Processes, 66, 102–110.
The effects of information-processing demands and social- Russo, J. E., Meloy, M. G., & Medvec, V. H. (1998). Predecisional
situational factors on the social decision making of children. distortion of product information. Journal of Marketing Re-
Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 43, 244–259. search, 35, 438–452.
Künzler, R., & Bakker, C. M. (2001). Female preferences for single Schlottmann, A. (2001). Children’s probability intuitions: Under-
and combined traits in computeranimated stickleback males. standing the expected value of complex gambles. Child Devel-
Behavioral Ecology, 12, 681–685. opment, 72(1), 103–122.

293
BETSCH AND GLÖCKNER

Schwoebel, J., Dews, S., Winner, E., & Srinivas, K. (2000). Oblig- Thagard, P. (1989). Explanatory coherence. Behavioral and Brain
atory processing of the Literal meaning of ironic utterances: Sciences, 12, 435–502.
Further evidence. Metaphor and Symbol, 15, 47–61. Thagard, P., & Millgram, E. (1995). Inference to the best plan: A
Simon, D., Krawczyk, D. C., & Holyoak, K. J. (2004). Construc- coherence theory of decision. In A. Ram & D. B. Leake (Eds.),
tion of preferences by constraint satisfaction. Psychological Goal-driven learning (pp. 439–454). Cambridge, MA: MIT
Science, 15, 331–336. Press.
Simon, D., Pham, L. B., Le, Q. A., & Holyoak, K. J. (2001). The Thomas, D. (1968). A child’s christmas in Wales. London, UK: J.M.
emergence of coherence over the course of decision making. Dent.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1973). Availability: A heuristic for
Cognition, 27, 1250–1260. judging frequency and probability. Cognitive Psychology, 5,
Simon, D., Snow, C. J., & Read, S. J. (2004). The redux of cog- 207–232.
nitive consistency theories: Evidence judgments by constraint Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgment under uncertainty:
satisfaction. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 86, Heuristics and biases. Science, 185, 1124–1131.
814–837. Wang, A. T., Lee, S. S., Sigman, M., & Dapretto, M. (2006). Neural
Simon, H. A. (1955). A behavioral model of rational choice. The basis of irony comprehension in children with autism: the role
Quarterly Journal of Economics, 69, 99–118. of prosody and context. Brain, 12, 932–943.
Simon, H. A. (1982). Models of bounded rationality. Cambridge, Winerman, L. (2005). Intuition [Special issue]. APA Monitor on
MA: MIT Press. Psychology, 36(3).
Downloaded by [Universitats Forschungsbiblio] at 07:00 24 November 2011

Svenson, O. (1992). Differentiation and consolidation theory of hu- Wundt, W. (1907). Outlines of psychology. Leipzig, Germany: Wil-
man decision making: A frame of reference for the study of helm Engelmann.
pre- and post-decision processes. Acta Psychologica, 80, 143– Zajonc, R. B. (1980). Feeling and thinking: Preferences need no
168. inferences. American Psychologist, 35, 151–175.

294

View publication stats

Вам также может понравиться