Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 25

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/236800275

Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia: Contemporary


Approaches and Misunderstandings

Article  in  Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology · March 2011


DOI: 10.1353/ppp.2011.0008

CITATIONS READS
61 538

3 authors, including:

Josef Parnas Dan Zahavi


University of Copenhagen University of Copenhagen
214 PUBLICATIONS   10,478 CITATIONS    116 PUBLICATIONS   4,528 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

Early detection and intervention in mental health View project

Schizophrenia as Self-disorder: Bridging the gap between brain-body and phenomenal experience. View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Josef Parnas on 15 August 2014.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


Access Provided by New Copenhagen University Library at 06/20/11 10:12AM GMT
Phenomenological
Psychopathology
and Schizophrenia:
Contemporary
Approaches and
Misunderstandings
Louis Sass, Josef Parnas, and
Dan Zahavi

T
Abstract: The present paper clarifies key issues in he phenomenological approach to
phenomenology and phenomenological psychopathol- schizophrenia has undergone something
ogy (especially of schizophrenia) through a critique of a renaissance in Anglophone psychiatry
of a recent article that addresses these topics. Topics
in recent years. There has been a proliferation of
include (1) Phenomenology’s role in clarifying issues
not amenable to purely empirical methods; (2) The works that focus on the nature of subjectivity in
relationship between a phenomenological approach schizophrenia and related disorders, and that take
(focusing on the subjective life of the patient) and em- inspiration from the work of such German and
pirical science, including neuroscience; (3) The nature French philosophers as Husserl, Heidegger, and
of self-experience, especially in its pre-reflective form Merleau-Ponty, and such classical psychiatrists
(“ipseity”—involving “operative intentionality”), as Minkowski, Blankenburg, and Binswanger
and its possible disturbance in schizophrenia (“hyper-
(Rulf 2003; Sass 2001a, 2001b). This trend in-
reflexivity” and “diminished self-affection”); (4) The
relationship between self-disturbance in schizophrenia
cludes predominantly theoretical articles, which
and disorders of both temporality and (what Husserl typically incorporate clinical material as well as
termed) “passive syntheses”; (5) The role of intentional reviews of empirical and experimental findings
or quasi-volitional processes in the perceptual (and in psychopathology. Some very recent examples
other) disorders in schizophrenia; (6) The nature and (since 2000) are studies of self-experience (Sass
diversity of phenomenology’s potential contribution to and Parnas 2003), temporal experience (Fuchs
the enterprise of “explanation”; and (7) The meaning 2005), delusions and delusional mood (Parnas
of several concepts: “hermeneutic” or “existential” ap-
and Sass 2001; Fuchs 2005), and psychiatric
proach, phenomenological “reflection,” and “negative
symptoms.” classification and diagnosis (Parnas & Zahavi
2002), as well as of values and disturbances of
Keywords: self-disorder, pre-reflective self-awareness, common-sense (Stanghellini 2001, 2004; Stang-
ipseity, hyperreflexivity, self-affection, phenomenologi-
hellini and Ballerini 2007), affect or emotion
cal reflection, phenomenological explanation
(Ratcliffe 2008; Sass 2007a), negative symptoms

© 2011 by The Johns Hopkins University Press


2  ■  PPP / Vol. 18, No. 1 / March 2011

(Sass 2003a), perception (Nelson and Sass 2008; There was, in fact, very little writing—at least in
Sass 2004c; Schwartz et al. 2005), and personhood English (for French and German contributions, see
and autonomy (Sass 2007b, 2011). A major event Tatossian 1979; Naudin 1997)—specifically treat-
of recent years is the appearance of a series of ing the phenomenology of schizophrenia in the
empirical studies that demonstrate the reality of 25 years between the publication of Laing’s book
clinical-phenomenal disorders of self-experience and the appearance, starting in the mid 1980s,
as a core factor in early schizophrenia and that of articles by several authors. These include Sass
differentiate diagnosis of schizophrenia-spectrum (1985, 1987, 1988a, 1990a, 1990b, 1992b)—cul-
from other forms of psychosis or psychopathol- minating in his books, Madness and Modernism:
ogy (Møller and Husby 2000; Parnas et al. 1998; Insanity in the Light of Modern Art, Literature,
Parnas et al. 2003; Parnas, Handest, et al. 2005; and Thought (1992a), and The Paradoxes of
Parnas, Møller, et al. 2005). Delusion (1994)—Schwartz and Wiggins (1987;
This trend does not, of course, represent the also Wiggins et al. 1990), Cutting and Dunne
first attempt to study subjectivity in schizophre- (1989), and Parnas and Bovet (1991; Bovet and
nia, nor is it the first time that the continental Parnas 1993) . A superb anthology of classical
phenomenological tradition has been introduced. European contributions on schizophrenia, edited
Both Mayer-Gross’s famous textbook of psychia- by John Cutting and Michael Shepherd, appeared
try (1954) and Fish’s Schizophrenia (Hamilton in 1987. Cutting’s (1997) book on brain laterality
1984, originally1962) attempted—nobly but had a strong phenomenological component. Now,
with limited success—to bring phenomenological however, we are seeing a reasonably broad-based
psychopathology into the mainstream of English- attempt to bring phenomenological perspectives
language psychiatry. The work of Karl Jaspers’ to bear on scientific psychiatry, particularly on
disciple, Kurt Schneider, on the “First Rank Symp- schizophrenia, in the now-dominant world of
toms” of schizophrenia, was clearly Jaspersian on Anglophone psychiatry and clinical psychology.
the methodological plane, but unfortunately was These recent developments in phenomeno-
interpreted more in an operational than a truly logical psychopathology coincide with significant
phenomenological sense. Existence, an anthol- trends in both the mental health professions and
ogy edited by Rollo May, Ernst Angel, and Henri the mind sciences. One such trend is a growing
Ellenberger (1958), influenced humanistic trends disillusionment, within mainstream psychiatry,
in American clinical psychology. An important with the extreme emphasis on operationalizable
precursor to the above-mentioned empirical concepts that began with the advent of DSM
work is the research on schizophrenia-patients’ III in 1982. A number of recent editorials by
experience of the so-called “basic symptoms” of key figures in North American and European
schizophrenia, carried out since the end of the psychiatry (Andreasen 2007; Maj 2005; see also
1960s by Huber, Klosterkötter, and colleagues in Mullen 2007; Parnas et al. 2008) have noted the
Germany (Klosterkötter 1988, 1992; Klosterkötter relative lack of real scientific progress in the study
et al. 1997, 2001). of schizophrenia and many other disorders, and
The most prominent Anglophone attempt to have related this to the loss of validity that can
emphasize the importance of the subjective di- occur when there is an over-focus on reliability
mension of schizophrenia was R. D. Laing’s first (operational concepts). These editorials have re-
and finest book, The Divided Self (1959), a work lated this lack of progress to the loss, which they
admired by many who remain skeptical of Laing’s lament, of the rich, psychopathological tradition
later contributions. The Divided Self, which uses of European psychiatry, which is strongly (but
ideas from Sartre, Heidegger, Minkowski, and not exclusively) rooted in phenomenology. This
Binswanger, was something of a bolt from the disillusionment coincides with a certain malaise,
blue. Laing’s own interests and influence were soon notable among younger psychiatrists and clinical
diverted in an anti-psychiatric and sometimes ro- psychologists, who are frustrated with the increas-
manticizing or otherwise anti-scientific direction. ingly mechanical role they are expected to play in
Sass, Parnas, and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia  ■  3

a clinical world defined by bureaucratic demands, efforts (Nelson, Sass, Skodlar et al. 2009; Nelson
and doubtful about a scientific world dominated et al 2008; Parnas 2005).
by empirical methodologies that can seem divorced
from significant theoretical issues. A Source of
Another, more broad-based trend is the disil- Misunderstandings
lusionment with purely neurocentristic, cognitiv-
ist, and computationalist approaches that seems In this context, it is surprising that, very re-
to be spreading among scholars and scientists cently, an article should have appeared, addressed
in philosophy and the various sciences of mind, to a general psychiatric audience, in which recent
brain, and behavior. One can find a diverse group trends in the phenomenological psychopathology
of thinkers including Dreyfus (1979), Varela et al. of schizophrenia and key notions of phenomeno-
(1991), Clark (1997), Gallagher (2005), Zahavi logical philosophy are presented in a manner that
(2005), Thompson (2007), and Gallagher and is not only confusing, but highly inaccurate. Rath-
Zahavi (2008), who all in various ways have er than clarifying matters, the article in question
criticized the standard picture by insisting on the blurs key theoretical issues and leaves the reader
need for a renewed focus on subjectivity and on with the impression that much of phenomeno-
the embodiment and embeddedness of the human logical psychiatry must be, at its core, an obscure
subject. More recently, the concepts of self and discipline, incomprehensible and somehow deeply
of self-experience have also gained something of anti-scientific in nature.
a renaissance in philosophy, psychology, and the The article in question, published in Current
cognitive sciences (cf. Gallagher and Shear 1999; Opinion in Psychiatry in 2007, was authored
Kircher and David 2003; Sass et al. 2000). by Aaron Mishara and carries the title “Missing
The revival of a phenomenological approach links in phenomenological clinical neuroscience:
to psychiatry precedes the most recent of these Why we still are not there yet.” Mishara’s critique
trends, but fits in comfortably with current de- primarily targets two articles by Sass and Parnas
velopments. The phenomenological approach (2003, 2007), but also criticizes Sass (1992a),
emphasizes the need to delve below superficial Parnas (2003), and Zahavi (2005). In his contribu-
levels of behavioral description or common-sense, tion, Mishara strives to offer an ambitious review
symptomatic descriptions (Parnas and Sass 2008; of the relationship between phenomenology and
Zahavi and Parnas 1998). By offering a richer and neuroscience, and to construct a stark opposition
more empirically grounded theoretical approach between what he calls “neo-phenomenology” ver-
to the understanding of abnormal action and sus “existential or hermeneutic phenomenology.”
experience, it promises an escape from the opera- Mishara wishes to associate the first term with the
tionalist cul-de-sac that contemporary psychiatry work of Sass, Parnas, and Zahavi, and the second
is in danger of entering. The phenomenological term with his own work and that of such figures
study of schizophrenia in particular is of signal as Binswanger, Blankenburg, Conrad, von Weiz-
importance, not only because of schizophrenia’s saecker, Matussek, and Wiggins and Schwartz. As
preeminent place in the history of psychiatry, we argue, however, the distinction in question is
but also because of the profound, enigmatic, and confused and misleading.1
potentially revelatory nature of the alterations The publication of Mishara’s account is not
of subjectivity and selfhood that it involves. The entirely to be lamented, however: it articulates
increased focus, over the last 15 years, on early certain misunderstandings that may be widespread
intervention for mental disorders, particularly psy- enough to be worth addressing in detail, thereby
chotic disorders, has particularly highlighted the giving us the opportunity to correct potential mis-
importance of understanding subjective experience apprehensions and to explain some basic points
in pre-schizophrenic and schizophrenic conditions, about our own approach and the phenomeno-
which may be relevant for the prediction and logical enterprise more generally. In the present
identification of high risk, as well as treatment article, we take his publication as an occasion for
4  ■  PPP / Vol. 18, No. 1 / March 2011

clarifying a number of important issues (sometimes mality in schizophrenia. Here Mishara rejects the
overlapping) concerning phenomenology and its claim that consciousness is as such characterized
role in the study of psychopathology in general by a pervasive but tacit dimension of pre-reflective
and schizophrenia in particular; in this way, we self-consciousness, and denies that self-disturbance
offer a discussion that should be of general interest is a central core feature of schizophrenia. We con-
(see also Gallagher and Zahavi 2008). The issues sider Mishara’s claims and criticisms to be both
treated below are the following: mistaken and misleading. We begin with general
1. The role of phenomenology in clarifying issues not methodological and philosophical issues, namely,
amenable to purely empirical methods. with Mishara’s views on the relevance of phenom-
2. The relationship between a phenomenological ap- enology, the notion of “constraint” (a term we
proach (focusing on the subjective life of the patient) use), and the nature of phenomenological “facts.”
and that of empirical science, including neurosci- Later we turn to selfhood and other topics.
ence. (This relationship involves what is sometimes
referred to as the “naturalizing” of phenomenology.)
3. The nature of self-experience, especially in its Nature and Role of
pre-reflective form, and its possible disturbance in Phenomenology
schizophrenia.
4. The relationship between self-disturbance in schizo- In his article, Mishara states that Sass and
phrenia and disorders both of temporality and of Parnas (2007) and Zahavi (2005) “proposed that
(what Husserl termed) “passive syntheses.” phenomenology is able to constrain neuroscience
5. The possible, contributing role of intentional or when applied to disorders such as schizophre-
quasi-volitional processes in the perceptual disorders nia” (Mishara 2007a, 559, emphasis added).
in schizophrenia. He explains this point by stating that, according
6. The nature—and especially the diversity—of phe-
to Sass, Parnas, and Zahavi, “phenomenology
nomenology’s potential contribution to the enterprise
of “explanation” (broadly understood, in contrast provides conclusive knowledge or limits, what
with “mere” description). Zahavi calls ‘facts’, about the patient’s subjective
7. We also provide a number of necessary clarifications: experience” (Mishara’s words). We are said to
of the meaning of a “hermeneutic” or an “existen- believe that these facts could (in Mishara’s words
tial” approach; of the nature and role of “reflection” once again) “be directly incorporated into clini-
in phenomenological accounts; and of the meaning cal neuroscience” without requiring any kind of
of the concept of “negative symptoms.”
“experimental procedure.” Mishara continues:
Mishara’s main justifications for distinguishing “Rather than furnishing hypotheses or testable
between what he calls “neo-phenomenology” and constructs to neuroscience, neo-phenomenology
“existential/hermeneutic phenomenology” are claims to circumvent experimental procedure by
two. The fact that his article vacillates between offering constraints about the nature of (human)
the two justifications, without distinguishing them subjectivity with a foundation in philosophical
clearly, adds to the confusion. One justification phenomenology.” He contrasts this with what he
is largely methodological in nature, having to do calls the “existential-phenomenological . . . view
with the status and role of phenomenology. Ac- that phenomenology provides initial systematic
cording to Mishara (2007a), whereas (so-called) means” for studying subjectivity and seeks only
“neo-phenomenology claims to circumvent experi- to “supply hypotheses for further experimental
mental procedures,” the (so-called) “existential study” (p. 560). Mishara’s account is problematic.
phenomenology” with which he associates himself Not only does he not grasp the standard meaning
is, by contrast, “in an excellent position to supply of “constrain” as this term is used in recent dis-
hypotheses [and “testable constructs”] for further cussions on the relation between phenomenology
experimental study” (pp. 559–60). The second and cognitive science, he also fails to capture our
justification is more substantive: it pertains to dis- own view of the matter, and ultimately provides a
cussions related to the structure of consciousness superficial picture of what the phenomenological
and the specific nature of the psychological abnor- tradition has to offer contemporary psychiatry or
Sass, Parnas, and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia  ■  5

the project of the “naturalization” of conscious- is simply to say that these facts are among those
ness (the inclusion of consciousness within a that an adequate neurobiology must ultimately
general scientific perspective). take into account. It would seem that any person
We agree, of course, that a major role for with a remotely phenomenological bent would
phenomenology is indeed to supply hypotheses have to accept this latter point; indeed, it should
for further empirical study. However, we reject even be accepted by reductionists who believe that
the idea that phenomenology’s relevance should consciousness is entirely dependent on the biologi-
be restricted to this role. Psychiatry, after all, is cal substrate. After all, conscious experience is “an
faced with a host of philosophical questions—for explanandum in its own right” (Chalmers, 1995,
example, questions concerning the nature of 209). And “without some idea . . . of what the
rationality, the definition of delusion, and the subjective character of experience is, we cannot
possibility of empathy with abnormal states of know what is required of physicalistic theory”
mind. To think that such questions can be settled (Nagel 1979, 71).
by clinical trials or other purely empirical methods This does not, by the way, rule out the possibil-
would amount to a kind of scientism that would ity that cognitive or neurobiological findings might
certainly be rejected by all the major theorists of actually suggest new ways of thinking about and
phenomenology. Phenomenology, together with describing aspects of phenomenal experience. On
other philosophical approaches, has something the contrary, we (like both Gallagher and Varela)
to say on these issues. are precisely arguing that the influence goes both
ways, that is, it would also be a question of letting
Mutual “Constraints”; phenomenology profit from—and be challenged
Phenomenological “Facts” by—empirical findings.2
When it comes to cashing out this idea about
To clarify phenomenology’s role within the mutuality or reciprocity in more concrete detail,
mind sciences, we must consider precisely what it various complementary proposals are currently on
means to say that phenomenology can constrain offer. One proposal, entitled neurophenomenol-
neuroscience. When using the term “constrain” ogy, was initially proposed by Varela (1996) and
(Sass and Parnas 2007, 73), we cited a well-known subsequently developed by Lutz (2002), Lutz and
paper by Gallagher (1997): “Mutual enlighten- Thompson (2003), and Thompson (2007). Here,
ment: Recent phenomenology in cognitive sci- the basic idea is to train experimental subjects to
ence.” In the next paragraph, we cited another gain greater intimacy with their own experiences.
well-known article: “Neurophenomenology,” in Subsequently, the subjects are asked to provide
which (the late) Francesco Varela (1996) speaks descriptions of these experiences using an open-
of “mutual” or “reciprocal constraints” between question format, thus minimizing the imposition of
“phenomenological accounts of the structure predetermined theoretical categories. The ensuing
of experience and their counterparts in cogni- descriptive categories are subsequently validated
tive science” (p. 343). Thompson (2007), who intersubjectively and then used to interpret corre-
collaborated extensively with Varela, clarifies: lated measurements of behavior and brain activity.
“By ‘reciprocal constraints’ [Varela] means that At the same time, however, it is also suggested that,
phenomenological analyses can help guide and say, a consideration of insights from neurobiol-
shape the scientific investigation of consciousness, ogy and dynamical systems theory can help us to
and that scientific findings can in turn help guide improve and refine the classical phenomenological
and shape the phenomenological investigations” analyses (see Varela 1996; Thompson 2007). How
(p. 329). is that supposed to happen?
The term “constrain” does not, then, mean The basic idea is quite simple: let us assume,
anything like “inhibit” or “dictate to in a rigid or for instance, that our initial phenomenological
unilateral fashion.” To say that the facts of subjec- description presents us with what seems to be a
tive life “constrain” neurobiological explanation simple and unified phenomenon. When studying
6  ■  PPP / Vol. 18, No. 1 / March 2011

the neural correlates of this phenomenon (e.g., “constraint” versus as a generative source of hy-
with magnetic resonance imaging), we discover potheses—is entirely spurious. Indeed, it is only
that two quite distinct mechanisms are involved, because experience is implicated in the overall
mechanisms that are normally correlated with causal/explanatory nexus (which is to say, that
distinct experiential phenomena, say, perception it serves as a “constraint”—according to the
and memory. This discovery might motivate us to standard understanding of “constrain”) that it
return to our initial phenomenological description could possibly be relevant for hypothesizing.
to see whether the phenomenon in question is truly It is precisely this kind of “mutual constraint”
as simple as we thought. Perhaps a more careful (between empirical data on neurodevelopmental
analysis will reveal that it harbors a concealed problems, phenomenological data on initial stages
complexity. However, it is important to empha- of the illness, and neurobiological data concern-
size that the discovery of a significant complexity ing ontogenesis of cortico-cortical connectivity)
on the subpersonal level—to stick to this simple that led one of the present authors to propose,
example—cannot by itself force us to refine or in 1996, a binding problem associated with the
revise our phenomenological description. It can, phenomenological core features of schizophrenia,
however, serve as motivation for further inquiry. within a distributed mis-connectivity model of
More recently, Gallagher (2003) has made a neurodevelopmental vulnerability to the illness
slightly different proposal that he has entitled (Parnas et al. 1996, 2001, 2002).
front-loaded phenomenology. Rather than focus- Before leaving the issue of methodological
ing on training experimental subjects, the idea is “constraints,” it is interesting to consider the
to start with the experimental design, and to allow peculiar way in which Mishara tries to establish
insights developed in phenomenological analyses our supposed commitment to the idea that phe-
to inform the way experiments are set up. To take nomenology can provide conclusive and substan-
a concrete example, let us consider the study of tive knowledge about the nature of the mind that
self-consciousness within developmental psychol- would determine the boundaries of neuroscientific
ogy, where the so-called “mirror-recognition task” research in a unidirectional manner. The textual
has occasionally been heralded as the decisive test evidence Mishara offers consists in only three
for self-consciousness (Lewis 2003). A phenom- quotations and references, all to works by Zahavi
enological approach suggests moving beyond (2004, 343; 2005, 136; see Mishara 2007a, 559).
reliance on mirror-recognition alone—which phe- These Zahavi references are quotations taken out
nomenologists would typically consider evidence of context or tendentious attempts to paraphrase.
for the presence of a rather sophisticated form of Indeed, Mishara himself seems to recognize this
self-consciousness—and attempting to detect the last point, for he immediately goes on to admit
presence of more primitive forms of propriocep- (quite correctly) that “Zahavi himself does not
tive body awareness (Zahavi 2005). To front-load endorse this position.” No quotations from Parnas
phenomenology, however, does not imply that one or Sass are offered. But where, then, is the evidence
simply presupposes or accepts well-rehearsed phe- that any of the three of us actually adopts the view
nomenological results. Rather, it involves testing Mishara attributes to us?
those results and, more generally, incorporates a A closely related misunderstanding concerns
dialectical movement between previous insights Mishara’s characterization of our understanding
gained in phenomenology and preliminary trials of phenomenological “facts.” Nowhere do we say
that will specify or extend these insights for pur- that phenomenological methods generate abso-
poses of the particular experiment or empirical lutely precise and certain descriptions that cannot
investigation (Gallagher and Zahavi 2008). possibly be criticized or improved upon—that is,
Once one grasps the actual (and, in this dis- that are not defeasible, in the sense of being in prin-
course, standard) meaning of “constrain,” one ciple open to revision or valid objection. It is odd,
immediately sees that the opposition Mishara then, to find Mishara claiming for himself the label
poses—between phenomenology serving as a of “hermeneutic phenomenology.” If hermeneutic
Sass, Parnas, and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia  ■  7

phenomenology means a phenomenology that 1973; Ricoeur 1992; Zahavi 1999].) This self or ipseity
rejects aspiration to apodictic certainty in favor of disturbance has two main aspects or features that may
a more humble understanding of the nature of the at first sound mutually contradictory, but are in fact
complementary. The first is hyper-reflexivity—which re-
phenomenological enterprise (i.e., as an enterprise
fers to a kind of exaggerated self-consciousness, that is,
that requires interpretation rather than offering a tendency to direct focal, objectifying attention toward
infallible description), then our work—like that processes and phenomena that would normally be “in-
of many others—certainly falls under the rubric habited” or experienced as part of oneself. The second
“hermeneutic.”3 Mishara (2007a) has no basis for is diminished self-affection—which refers to a decline
claiming that we believe our phenomenological in the (passively or automatically) experienced sense
accounts to be “immune to error” (p. 561). Nor of existing as a living and unified subject of awareness.
does Mishara offer any textual evidence to sustain “Ipseity disturbance” also involves a concomi-
his claim that “neo-phenomenology” “claims to tant disturbance of the field of awareness that we
circumvent experimental procedures.” Actually, a label “disturbed hold” or “grip” (Sass 2004c; Sass
considerable amount of empirical work has been and Parnas 2003, 436).
done and is underway to test the validity and rel-
HYPERREFLEXIVITY: The notion of hyperreflexivity
evance of our phenomenologically inspired model
includes some fairly volitional, quasi-volitional, or intel-
of schizophrenia (see further below). lectual processes, which we term “hyper-reflectivity.”5
However: the hyperreflexivity in question is not, at
The Ipseity- or Self- its core, an intellectual, volitional, or “reflective”
kind of self-consciousness; nor is it merely an intensi-
Disturbance (IHM) View fied awareness of something that would normally be
The second major way in which Mishara distin- taken as an object (e.g., in the case of an adolescent’s
guishes between what he calls “neo-phenomenolo- self-consciousness about his or her appearance). Most
gy” and “existential phenomenology” is by saying basic to schizophrenia is a kind of “operative” hyper-
reflexivity that occurs in an automatic fashion. This
that, whereas the former postulates disorders of
has the effect of disrupting awareness and action by
selfhood (ipseity-hyperreflexivity model [IHM]) means of an automatic popping-up or popping-out of
as the core of psychopathology of schizophrenia, phenomena and processes that would normally remain
the latter emphasizes, rather, disorders of “passive in the tacit background of awareness (where they serve
syntheses,” binding, temporalization, and percep- as a medium of implicit self-affection), but that now
tual organization. In his article, the IHM becomes come to be experienced in an objectified and alienated
an object of Mishara’s passionate attack.4 Here, manner (see Merleau-Ponty 1962, p. xviii re: “operative
intentionality”—fungierende Intentionalität).
however, Mishara misunderstands most of the key
elements of our ipseity-, self-disturbance, or IHM Phenomenally speaking, hyperreflexivity can
view, which are clearly laid out in the two articles be manifest as an emergence or intensification of
he targets (Sass and Parnas 2003, 2007). Briefly, experience as such or a prominence of proximal
this model claims that instability of pre-reflective over distal aspects of stimuli (see e.g. Sass 1994 re:
self-awareness is a core, generative feature of “phantom concreteness”), or as focal awareness
schizophrenia; the disorder affects what in cogni- of kinesthetic bodily sensations, “inner speech,”
tive literature is called minimal or core self. Here or the processes or presuppositions of thinking.
are some key passages from our account (Sass and
DIMINISHED SELF-AFFECTION involves diminished
Parnas, 2007, 68–70, unless otherwise noted). sense of being a vital, first-person perspective on the
IPSEITY DISTURBANCE: [T]he core abnormality in world. It pertains to a fundamental sense of existing as
schizophrenia is a particular kind of disturbance of an experiencing entity, . . . as a kind of implicit subject-
consciousness and, especially, of the sense of self or pole that would normally serve as the vital center-point
ipseity that is normally implicit in each act of aware- of subjective life. . . . [One] patient with schizophrenia
ness. (Ipseity derives from ipse, Latin for “self” or described the condition of lacking this crucial if inef-
“itself.” Ipse-identity or ipseity refers to a crucial sense fable self-affection that is essential to normal ipseity: “I
of self-sameness, of existing as a subject of experience was simply there, only in that place, but without being
that is at one with itself at any given moment [Henry present.” (Blankenburg 1971, 42; 1991, 77)
8  ■  PPP / Vol. 18, No. 1 / March 2011

The hyperreflexivity and diminished self- This includes descriptive and follow-up studies
affection central in schizophrenia involve distinc- of different diagnostic categories (Vollmer-Larsen
tive disruptions of the tacit-focal structure of 2008), predictive work on early psychosis (see
experience. below), and also some experimental work correlat-
[T]hese two features are best conceptualized not as ing anomalies of experience with neurocognitive
separate processes but as mutually implicative aspects measures (Parnas et al. 2001).
or facets of the intentional activity of awareness. Thus, Thus, in contemporary psychiatry the notion
whereas the notion of hyperreflexivity emphasizes the of self-disorders as the initial, core features of
way in which something normally tacit becomes focal schizophrenia was almost simultaneously first
and explicit, the notion of diminished self-affection reported from a Danish study of 19 first-onset
emphasizes a complementary aspect of this very same
schizophrenia-spectrum patients (Parnas et al.
process—the fact that what once was tacit is no longer
being inhabited as a medium of taken-for-granted self-
1998) and a Norwegian study of 20 first admitted
hood. (Sass and Parnas 2003, 430) schizophrenia patients (Møller and Husby 2000).
These findings were subsequently supported in a
It makes little sense, incidentally, to character- longitudinal study of 155 first admitted patients,
ize our ipseity or IHM view by using a simple of whom about 60% suffered from schizophrenia
opposition between “too much” versus “too or schizotypal disorders (Handest and Parnas
little” self-experience—as do Lysaker and Lysaker 2005; Parnas, Handest, et al. 2005). These pa-
(2008a, 32) in their interesting study of dialogical tients have been reassessed at a 5-year follow-up,
dimensions of schizophrenia. On our view, there showing that self-disorders are predictive of new
is a sense in which the person with schizophrenia incident cases of schizophrenia spectrum disorders
has both too little sense of self (diminished self- (Vollmer-Larsen 2008). A separate study compar-
affection) and too much self-consciousness (hy- ing residual schizophrenia patients with remitted
perreflexivity). Selfhood is too complex an issue psychotic bipolar illness patients demonstrated
to lend itself to unidimensional characterization that self-disorders were characteristic of schizo-
and requires, among other things, sophisticated phrenia (Parnas et al. 2003), suggesting a certain
phenomenological analysis (Zahavi 2005). Before specificity to schizophrenia spectrum disorders.
elaborating on theoretical issues, we outline recent Currently, several other samples are being studied
empirical work that supports our self-disorder (Skodlar et al. 2008), and data analyses are being
position. conducted on opportunistic samples of high-risk
and genetic research performed in Copenhagen.
Empirical Support for the Similar research projects and studies on early
Ipseity-Disturbance (IHM) identification of schizophrenia are being under-
View taken in several European countries, Israel, and
Australia. A phenomenologically oriented, semi-
Like virtually all scientific work, the IHM is structured psychiatric interview—the EASE scale
partly rooted in theoretical work, including such (Parnas, Møller, et al. 2005)—has been developed
psychopathological studies as Sass (1987, 1992a, and shown to achieve good inter-rater reliability
Chapter 7) and Spitzer (1988), as well as philo- (Vollmer-Larsen et al. 2007). The EASE scale’s
sophical work including Henry (1973, 1975) and description of self-disorders seems to have satisfied
Zahavi (1999), among many others. It is important a clinical void as testified by the fact that the scale
to point out, however, that our phenomenological has so far been translated into seven languages.
claims concerning anomalous self-experience as In summary, there is now considerable empirical
a core feature of schizophrenia-spectrum disor- evidence available that shows “trait-like” presence
ders, is not a product of arm-chair theorizing or of self-disorders in the schizophrenia spectrum
anecdotal discussion, as Mishara portrays it, but disorders. The measures of self-disorder are now
derives, in large measure, from years of clinical being included in studies targeting early recogni-
experience and considerable empirical research. tion and treatment of schizophrenia.
Sass, Parnas, and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia  ■  9

In his article, Mishara omits all the (then hara seems to think. It is a passive and automatic
available) empirical studies mentioned. Oddly, process that must be regarded as the diachronic
however, he does mention one vignette from a and synchronic prerequisite or precondition for
conceptual publication by Parnas and Handest any more substantial or elaborate sense of self.
(2003), only to warn his readers that “we must Having or embodying a first-person perspec-
be careful not to draw conclusions from anecdotal tive does not, incidentally, require being able to
self-reports” (Mishara 2007a, 565, italics added). articulate it linguistically. Indeed, it provides an
experiential grounding of the latter possibility
The Notion of Ipseity or Pre- All the major figures in phenomenology—includ-
Reflective Self-Awareness ing Husserl, Merleau-Ponty, Sartre, and Michel
Henry—considered a minimal form of self-con-
Mishara (2007a) also gets the central theoreti- sciousness to be an integral part of experience.
cal features of our view on self-disorder (ipseity This, for instance, is what Sartre meant when he
disturbance) wrong in various ways. Consider declared that self-consciousness constitutes the
his statement that we view “the core deficit in mode of being of intentional consciousness (Sartre
schizophrenia to be on the level of intentionality 1956, liv).
of fully constituted objects and self” (p. 560, italics
added). This is incorrect. The Issue of Phenomenological
The IHM model claims that a central phenom-
enon of the schizophrenia spectrum disorders is
“Reflection”
a disturbance in pre-reflective self-awareness (or Mishara (2007a) claims that Zahavi’s (2005)
ipseity, from Latin: ipse = self, itself), that is, a argument for the existence of a pervasive pre-
disturbance of the very mineness or first-person reflective self-awareness (ipseity) is tenuous
perspective that characterizes any experience. because of numerous conceptual problems. He
What do we mean by first-person perspective, then mentions the following difficulty: there is
by pre-reflective self-awareness, and what does the no way of knowing whether what I describe in
mineness of experience refer to? reflection was truly there before reflection, because
When we refer to the mineness of experience, the reflecting itself may have somehow added or
we are not referring to a specific content of experi- inserted precisely those aspects I was looking for
ence, like yellow, or being salty or spongy. We are (Mishara 2007a, 561). As is widely acknowl-
referring to the first-personal presence, givenness- edged, recognition of this methodological or
to-me, or perspectival ownership of experience, epistemological problem is an utter commonplace
to the fact that experience feels like something in phenomenological discussion. It was broached
for somebody. For a subject to own something by Husserl himself (see, e.g., his discussion with
in a perspectival sense, is for the experience in H.J. Watt in §79 of Ideas I [Husserl 1982]) and
question to present itself in a distinctive manner was later discussed by numerous authors within
to the subject whose experience it is. Ipseity could the phenomenological tradition (cf. Chapter 4 in
be defined as the self-presence (the presence to Zahavi 2005).
itself) of the self-as-subject. These pre-reflective All the phenomenologists recognized that,
aspects of experience contribute to what we (and rather than merely copying or repeating the origi-
others) call the minimal self (cf. Zahavi 1999, nal experience, reflection actually transforms it, or
2005).6 We admit, however, that an analysis of as Husserl explicitly admitted, it alters it (Husserl
the minimal self is something of an abstraction 1950, 72; 1987, 89). Husserl spoke of reflection as
as long as it fails to include the temporal dimen- a process that discloses, disentangles, explicates,
sion (more about this in a moment). The basic or articulates, and accentuates (herausgehoben) all
minimal self-experience to which we refer is not those components and structures that were implic-
something willed or explicitly assumed, nor does itly contained in the pre-reflective experience (Hus-
it involve reference to a full-fledged self, as Mis- serl 1984, 244; 1966a, 129; 1966b, 205, 236).
10  ■  PPP / Vol. 18, No. 1 / March 2011

One might see the phenomenological position view is not, however, unprecedented. Indeed, on
as being situated between two extremes. On one one reading, this is precisely the position adopted
hand, we have the view that reflection merely cop- by many “higher-order thought” theorists in
ies or mirrors pre-reflective experience faithfully; contemporary analytic philosophy of mind. Some
on the other, the view that reflection distorts lived of them have bitten the bullet and accepted the
experience irredeemably. The middle course is to consequences of their position regarding the as-
recognize that reflection involves both a gain and cription of phenomenal consciousness to creatures
a loss. For Husserl, Sartre, and Merleau-Ponty, that lack the capacity for higher-order first-person
reflection is constrained by what is pre-reflectively thoughts. Carruthers, for instance, holds the view
lived through; it is answerable to experiential that animals (and children under the age of three)
facts and is not constitutively self-fulfilling. But are simply blind to the very existence of their own
at the same time, they recognized that reflection mental states; and that there is, in fact, nothing at
qua thematic self-experiences does not simply re- all that it is like for them to feel pain or pleasure
produce the lived experiences unaltered, and that (Carruthers 1998, 216). Such a position certainly
this may be precisely what makes reflection cogni- seems counterintuitive. And as Carruthers himself
tively valuable. As Husserl put it, in the beginning notes, it might have profound implications for
we are confronted with a dumb experience that our moral attitudes toward animals and animal
through reflection must then be made to articulate suffering (Carruthers 1996, 221). Is this the kind
its own sense (Husserl 1950, 77; Merleau-Ponty of position that Mishara is endorsing?
1945, 207).
A widely held view, to which we adhere, then, Self-Awareness and
is that phenomenological reflection does contain Absorption in the World
the potential for a kind of iatrogenic error, and
that this is one reason why its results cannot be Throughout his writings, Husserl, the founder
considered to have the status of apodictic certi- of phenomenology, is very explicit in arguing that
tude. This does not, however, preclude the value self-consciousness—rather than being something
of phenomenological reflection so long as this that only occurs during exceptional circumstances,
reflection is imbued with a self-critical awareness namely, whenever we direct explicit attention to
of precisely such dangers. Moreover, as Husserl our conscious life—is a feature characterizing
argued, any skeptical claim to the effect that reflec- normal human subjectivity as such, no matter
tion necessarily falsifies the lived experiences and what worldly entities the subject might otherwise
that they consequently elude it completely is self- be conscious of and occupied with. As Husserl
refuting: after all, this very claim must presuppose for instance puts it in Zur Phänomenologie der
knowledge of those very same lived experiences, Intersubjektivität II, “To be a subject is to be in
and how should one obtain that except through the mode of being aware of oneself” (Husserl
some kind of reflection (Husserl 1982, §79)? 1973, 151). It is clearly erroneous, then, for Mis-
Thus, rather than adding new, distorting hara to take Husserl as supporting his claim that
components and structures to the experience world-absorption and self-awareness are mutually
reflected upon, a reflection might, at best, simply exclusive (Mishara 2007a, 560–1). When Husserl
be accentuating structures already inherent in the talks about Selbstverlorenheit in connection with
lived experience. But how does this apply to the our intentional absorption in the world, he does
specific issue of the first-personal givenness of ex- not refer to a complete loss of self, as Mishara
perience that we were just discussing? To claim, as (2007a) seems to think (p. 561), but to the ab-
Mishara does, that it is reflection that creates the sence of a thematic or reflective self-experience
distinctive first-personal quality of experience, that (see Zahavi 1999).
experience lacked such qualities before becoming Heidegger—a key figure for “hermeneutic” and
the object of a first-person thought, is to attribute “existential” trends in phenomenology—is also
quite exceptional powers to reflection. Such a referring to pre-reflective self-experience when
Sass, Parnas, and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia  ■  11

he argues that the self is present and implicated an object-like or representational mode—what
in all of its intentional (world- or object-directed) he now calls “self-awareness (in terms of self-
comportments; that the co-disclosure of the self reference)” or an “image-representation of self,
belongs to intentionality as such (Heidegger 1989, that is, having a self, a “me,” rather than being a
225). Heidegger also wrote that every worldly self, an ‘I’” (p. 560). Yet the distinction between
experiencing involves a certain component of pre-reflective self-experience and the experience
self-familiarity, and that every experiencing is of self-as-object is at the very heart of the articles
characterized by the fact that “I am always some- by Sass and Parnas (2003; 2007) that Mishara
how acquainted with myself” (Heidegger 1993, criticizes and a book by Zahavi that Mishara also
251; 1989, 225). cites (Zahavi 2005; also 1999).
Mishara’s draws a supposed contrast between, In summary: the IHM does not focus on distur-
on one hand, Sass and Parnas’s (2003) claim that bance of a fully constituted self or self-as-object
“we are self-aware through our practical absorp- nor of fully constituted object, nor does it speak
tion in the world of objects” (p. 430), and, on of a focal, thematic intentionality. Rather, we
the other hand, what he calls the “existential speak of disturbed or unstable preconditions for
phenomenological” notion that what he terms the normal, concordant, and smooth articulation
“self-awareness” and “absorption in experience” of the self-object correlation. Once one grasps this
are “mutually exclusive” (Mishara 2007a, 560). key point, one sees that the dynamic, ever-shifting
There is, in fact, no contrast here at all: it is just qualities of self-experience that Mishara (2007a)
that two different notions of self, both clearly rightly emphasizes (p. 563) are, in fact, perfectly
distinguished in much of the phenomenological consistent with what we mean by ipseity. It is
tradition, are being conflated by Mishara. As obvious that the pre-reflective self would not be a
Sass and Parnas emphasize, the self-awareness static entity, but something more like an ongoing
(ipseity) to which they primarily refer is not self- process that must exist and constantly reconstitute
as-intentional-object-of-experience, but rather itself in time.7
the implicit or pre-reflective self-awareness of the
self-as-subject—which most phenomenologists see “Passive Syntheses” and
as a concomitant of object awareness and a pre- “Operative Intentionality”
requisite of reflective self-awareness (for details see
Zahavi 1999; 2005). Thus, Paul Ricoeur (1966, As a supposedly “existential-phenomenological
60–1), the most prominent synthesizer of phe- response” or alternative view, Mishara (2007a)
nomenology and hermeneutics, criticizes the view proposes that the primary disorder of schizophre-
that “consciousness turned toward the other [is] nia resides in “passive syntheses” of “pre-attentive
unconscious of itself” and that “self-consciousness binding between subcomponents of the self (e.g.,
[he is referring to pre-reflective self-consciousness I, me, and mine. . .)” (p. 562). (He does not, how-
or ipseity] corrod[es] the consciousness which is ever, say much about how this would cash out in
directed toward something other than itself.” fundamental clinical features of schizophrenia.)
It is noteworthy that, here again, there seems to Mishara wants to offer the reader a polarized
be slippage in Mishara’s treatment of the issues: choice between ipseity, on one hand, and passive
at one point, he seems to acknowledge the non– synthesis or temporality, on the other, as potential
object-like and (in a sense) non-representational candidates of a generative disorder in schizophre-
nature of ipseity: citing Sass and Parnas (2007), he nia. In this way, he falsely reifies phenomenological
notes that the IHM model speaks of a “disruption concepts into mutually exclusive natural-kind–like
of a tacitly functioning operative intentionality categories, while failing to grasp key distinctions
which forms the background of consciousness” between levels of discourse and of psychological
(Mishara 2007a, 560). But then, when he at- reality.
tempts to argue against ipseity’s fundamental role Mishara thus fails to grasp that, when we speak
in experience, he clearly conflates ipseity with of such phenomena as schizophrenic autism, lack
12  ■  PPP / Vol. 18, No. 1 / March 2011

of self-affection, operative hyperreflexivity, lack automatic or ‘passive syntheses’ that structure


of common sense, loss of natural self-evidence, the basic act of consciousness and constitute a
diminished feelings of immersion, perplexity, and person’s most immediate and fundamental rela-
other aspects of the ipseity disturbance, we are tionship to self and to world” (Sass 2003a, 167,
also referring to the phenomenal manifestations 157). Earlier Sass (1992a) noted the possibility of
of disturbed passive synthetic processes. Our use neurophysiological “disturbance of those ‘lower’
of the term “operative intentionality,” coined by and more automatic processes that normally al-
Husserl and elaborated by Merleau-Ponty, refers low for spontaneity while providing a sense of
precisely to the tacit, pre-objectival, largely “pas- natural embeddedness in the practical and social
sive” processes that found the coherence of the world” (p. 396).
experiential field of the embedded subject (Sass Mishara’s characterization of our position as
2003a , 157; Sass and Parnas 2007, 69, 82–85). one that views schizophrenia as essentially deter-
Mishara (2007a) does in one passage (p. 560) note mined by “higher” or volitional processes is thus
our use of the phrase “operative intentionality,” a misrepresentation of what is, in fact, an attempt
but then ignores this key point when he goes on to demonstrate the complexity of the interaction
to criticize our position. of intentional/reflective and non-intentional or
In a recent article by Uhlhaas and Mishara “operative” factors.
(2007) our IHM or ipseity-disturbance approach In a recent article, Lysaker and Lysaker (2008b)
is described as being essentially a top-down model adopt this mistaken view, portraying Sass as plac-
that emphasizes “deficits in higher cognitive func- ing exclusive emphasis on the “withering” effect
tions” or “an excess of rationality and reflective- of an “inward gaze of radical intensity” (p. 335).
ness” (pp. 142–3, 150). Uhlhaas and Mishara As their citations and phrasings indicate, their
describe Sass (1992a) and Sass and Parnas (2003) discussion of Sass’s views derives largely from a
as “claim[ing] that fragmentation and destruction single, second-hand source: a paper by Mishara
of the self come from above by means of an excess (2004). They cite only one paper by Sass (2000),
of rationality or hyper ‘self-consciousness’” (p. while ignoring passages from that paper that
146). As summaries of the IHM or Sass’s current contradict theirs and Mishara’s portrayal. The
or earlier writings, these are clearly misreadings. Lysakers’ uncritical acceptance of Mishara’s inter-
Hyperreflexivity certainly can involve intel- pretation mars the treatment of phenomenology in
lectual or volitional processes, which can indeed their otherwise useful review article, and seems to
have pathogenetic importance. (The parallel have lead them into absurdities of which they are
with modernism makes these processes especially perhaps unaware. Thus, they portray Parnas and
salient in Sass’s Madness and Modernism.) But Sass as having incompatible views when, in reality,
contrary to what Uhlhaas and Mishara imply, both Parnas and Sass have been close collaborators for
Sass and Sass and Parnas have stated explicitly ten years, with congruent views as co-authors of
that hyperreflexivity should not be equated with papers on self-disorder and the phenomenology
intellectual or volitional processes of a “higher” of schizophrenia.
nature—which might better be termed “hyper- Also misleading is the Lysakers’ (2008b, 335)
reflectivity”—but also involves the popping out, reference to what they call “Mishara’s suggestion”
in a kind of automatic fashion, of phenomena that (emphasis added) regarding the core pathogenetic
would not normally be in the focus of awareness. role of disruption of “bodily systems that allow
Sass (2003b, 249) and Sass and Parnas (2007, 69, persons, without self-conscious effort, to suddenly
82–85) term this latter process “operative hyper- attend to novel information.” In fact, the pathoge-
reflexivity.” They state that the operative type is netic significance (for schizophrenic cognition) of
likely in fact to be more primary in a pathogenetic disruption of automatic processes that normally
sense than is the reflective type of hyperreflexivity orient attention toward the novel, is perfectly
(p. 83),8 “affecting what Blankenburg (following explicit in work by Hemsley and Gray, who em-
Husserl) calls the ‘fundamental receptivity’ of the phasize disorders of the hippocampus-based
Sass, Parnas, and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia  ■  13

“comparator system” (Hemsley 1987, 2005). Also neuroscience,” Mishara tends to oversimplify,
mistaken is the Lysakers’ presentation of this view misrepresent, and offer misleading polarization
as somehow antithetical to Sass’s position (also of alternatives. So far we have focused primar-
implied by Uhlhaas and Mishara 2007, 150, who ily on his polemical treatment of our own work.
cite Hemsley). Indeed, this view is perhaps the Oversimplification and polarization are also
main neurocognitive hypothesis Sass singles out characteristic of his conceptualizations of the
for its compatibility with his own position (see possible underlying psychopathology of schizo-
references in Sass 1992a; 2007a, 83, and other ar- phrenia. Both tendencies emerge with clarity if
ticles).9 In Madness and Modernism, Sass (1992a, we compare Mishara’s with Sass’s discussion of
228) discusses the role such factors might play the German Gestalt psychiatrist Matussek’s ideas
in self-fragmentation and bodily alienation—the about prodromal features (including the so-called
very point the Lysakers ascribe to a 2005 publica- Wahrnehmungstarre) and of the relevance of
tion by Mishara. The compatibility of Hemsley’s Wolfgang Blankenburg’s work for understanding
comparator approach with Sass is acknowledged negative symptoms, and also Mishara’s attack on
in Hemsley (1998).10 Sass and Parnas’s (2007) exploration of the pos-
sible explanatory relevance of phenomenology.
Temporality and Self-
Experience Die Wahrnehmungstarre and
Here we will not attempt to discuss, in any the Existential Complexity of
detail, the relationship between temporality and Schizophrenic Symptoms
self-experience. Clearly, however, there is some-
In Madness and Modernism (1992a, Chapter
thing absurd, from a phenomenological stand-
2), Sass uses the phrase “Truth-taking stare” to
point, about treating self-experience and temporal
capture the phenomenon described in German
experience as if these were distinct faculties of
the mind—as Mishara (2007a, 565) seems to do psychiatry by the term Wahrnehmungstarre. Wah-
when arguing that temporality is more basic than rnehmungstarre refers to the fixed gaze that can be
self in the schizophrenia disturbance. Indeed the especially common in early phases of schizophre-
central point of Zahavi’s influential interpretation nia; it would typically be translated as “rigidity
of Husserl’s writings on time was precisely that of perception” (as both Sass 1992a, 423, n4 and
the latter’s notion of inner time-consciousness Mishara 2007a, 564n note). In his article, Mishara
amounts to a form of pre-reflective self-awareness claims that Sass’s use of the phrase “truth-taking”
(Zahavi 1999, 2003a, 2003b). is a “fanciful but apocryphal” (p. 564) mistransla-
The temporal distortions of schizophrenia have tion, which suggests that Sass misunderstands the
long been recognized, in both the experimental meaning of the German term Wahrnehmungstarre,
and phenomenological literature on schizophrenia which means “perceptual rigidity”; and that this is
(e.g., Bovet and Parnas 1993; Minkowski 1927; one indication of what Mishara calls a gross lapse
1933/2005). Before being convinced that tempo- of “textual/philological accuracy” that should
rality in particular is playing a foundational role call Sass’s scholarly reliability and hermeneutic
in the pathogenesis of schizophrenia, it would be competence into question. Mishara goes so far as
necessary to show (at least) that (A) the disorder is to accuse Sass of “overlook[ing] the fundamental
reasonably specific to schizophrenia in particular hermeneutic principles” by “granting [himself]
and (B) the temporal abnormality is more striking the license to slip at these basic levels of textual-
than other abnormalities in schizophrenia (thereby philological accuracy (e.g., translation, historical
addressing some of the concerns raised long ago context, or careful and correct citing of sources)”
by Chapman and Chapman 1973). Mishara has (p. 564f).
not addressed either of these concerns. It is not difficult to show that the misunder-
By now it should be clear that in his article, standings and textual/philological “lapses” are
“Missing links in phenomenological clinical entirely Mishara’s. This should be apparent from
14  ■  PPP / Vol. 18, No. 1 / March 2011

Mishara’s apparent failure to take into account the “absurd” to claim that schizophrenic states are
following endnote, which is appended to Sass’s first entirely under the patient’s control, and “foolish
mention of the term Wahrnehmungstarre: “War- to view schizophrenia as purely volitional and
hrnehmung means ‘perception’ or ‘observation’ entirely self-aware” (p. 114).
in German. I have chosen to translate this in an Mishara’s attempt to appropriate for himself
unusually literal way—as ‘truth-taking’—because the label “existential phenomenology” is peculiar.
this seems better to capture the schizophrenic The approach Mishara offers in his article fails, in
experience in question” (Sass 1992a, 44, 423). fact, to go beyond a rather mechanical or passive
Wahr in German means “true,” as in the vision of the nature of schizophrenia, in which
term “Wahrheit,” meaning “truth.” Nehmung is the patient’s role is simply to be afflicted with
derived from “nehmen” as in “to take.” (Starre disturbances of passive synthesis; little if anything
means “stiffness” or “rigidity.”) The above-quoted is said about broader human or “existential”
note makes it perfectly obvious that Sass was de- consequences or about the patient’s conscious and
liberately and overtly using a kind of poetic license self-conscious project of “being-in-the-world.” By
(in accordance with the etymology of the parts of contrast, much of the work that Mishara criticizes
the word, and with full knowledge of the standard does explore these aspects in considerable depth
meaning of Wahrnehmung) to convey a sense of (see especially Sass 1992a, 2003a, 2004a; Sass and
the patient’s experience of a kind of revelation that Parnas 2007). Recently, Sass has focused on the
can accompany the fixed or rigid stare common nature of both personhood (2007b) and autonomy
in prodromal schizophrenia. There is, incidentally, (2011) in schizophrenia, noting, for example, that
something of a tradition of this kind of creative schizophrenia, a heterogeneous condition, can
etymology within phenomenology, especially in sometimes involve not simple diminishment of
the later Heidegger. autonomy, but more complex disruptions of the
Mishara commits other “textual/philological normal balance between independence and de-
lapses” against both Sass and Matussek. At one pendence or between autonomy and heteronomy
point, Mishara (2007a, 564) criticizes Sass for Mishara’s overly mechanical portrayal of
not following Matussek’s lead more closely, and passive syntheses seems particularly unsuited
thereby failing to appreciate the role of “rigidity to accounting for the remarkable variability of
or attentional capture” while overemphasizing schizophrenic symptoms and cognitive/affective
instead what Sass calls a “mode of deliberateness abnormalities, which as often noted (e.g., Bleuler
and hyperawareness.” In fact, Sass (1992a, 72, 1950, 72) may vary with context, motivation,
427f, notes 43, 44) criticizes Matussek’s (Gestalt) and attitude. It is noteworthy, for example, that
theoretical account for downplaying the role of cognitive and perceptual disorganization is by
intentionality, while noting that, in his clinical de- no means constant, and often disappears in the
scriptions, Matussek emphasizes both intentional presence of a strong motivation toward practical
and non-intentional aspects. Matussek (1987) activity (for references see Sass 1992a, Chapter
does say that the schizophrenic “is held captive by 1, p. 24 and notes 47, 48, 49; Chapter 2, p. 71
the object”; but he also writes, “The schizophrenic and notes 105, 112). In this sense it seems to be
. . . is capable, to a much greater degree, of fixing linked up with particular orientations of the self
his attention on an isolated object,” noting the (including forms of reflexivity and self-affection).
patient’s “ability” and “pleasure” in doing so (p. An understanding of ipseity disturbances is also
93–4, emphasis added). relevant for conceptualizing psychotherapeutic
Mishara’s characterization of Sass displays a interventions. It suggests the potential danger in
lack of familiarity with the arguments put forward overemphasizing certain forms of confrontation
in the works he criticizes. In writing on schizo- and self-reflection in the therapeutic process. It
phrenia, Sass never denies the role of deficien- may also help to illuminate the potentially agen-
cies, dysfunctions, or other forms of “affliction.” tive role of the patient, and thereby suggest more
Indeed, Sass (1992a, 73) states that it would be subtle ways of helping patients both to identify
Sass, Parnas, and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia  ■  15

with their experiences and to engage in the thera- 2001, 319–20), actually describes schizophrenia
peutic encounter (Nelson, Sass, and Skodlar 2009). simplex (following ICD-10) in clear negative-
symptom terms, namely, as “exhibit[ing] the basic
Negative Symptoms but not the accessory symptoms of schizophrenia,”
as being “fairly undramatic and inconspicuous in
In the same paragraph in which Mishara ques- its own right,” as manifesting “decline in total
tions Sass’s translation of Wahrnehmungstarre, he performance,” and as having the “characteristic
accuses Sass of another scholarly error; but once ‘negative’ features of residual schizophrenia (e.g.,
again, it is Mishara who commits errors of both blunting of affect, loss of volition) [which] develop
fact and logic. Mishara (2007a, 565) says that the without being preceded by any overt psychotic
phrase “negative symptoms” had not been applied symptoms.” If this is not a negative-symptom
to schizophrenia at the time that the phenomeno- syndrome, what is?
logical psychiatrist Blankenburg published his
book, The loss of natural self-evidence, in 1971,
and that for this reason it is inappropriate for Sass
Phenomenological
to consider the book to be relevant to what we Explanation
now call “negative symptoms.” We end by considering the important but
As it happens, Mishara is wrong on the histori- complex topic of phenomenology’s relevance for
cal point: several French psychiatrists, including explanation. We approach this issue by discussing
De Clerambault, Nayrac, and Ey, spoke of negative the inaccuracies in Mishara’s characterization of
symptoms in schizophrenia quite early in the twen- Sass and Parnas (2007), “Explaining schizophre-
tieth century (Berrios 1985, 1991). This historical nia: The relevance of phenomenology.” Mishara
error is almost beside the point, however. Even describes Sass and Parnas as offering a “proposal
if Mishara had been factually correct, his point to conflate explanation and understanding” in
would amount to a non sequitur that, if taken their 2007 article, and as somehow suggesting
seriously, would preclude our finding much of that phenomenological explanation need “not
contemporary relevance in older works of psycho- rely on experimental procedure.” He also states
pathology, which often apply somewhat different that “Sass and Parnas opt to associate their phe-
terminology to recognizable conditions that now nomenology with everyday explanation” (p. 563).
have different labels. (Often, of course, the over- Each of these three statements is flatly mistaken.
lapping of categories is only partial, and this com- It is not surprising, then, that in the paragraphs
plicates the comparisons.) Mishara (2007a) also containing these statements, Mishara offers virtu-
states that what Blankenburg calls “schizophrenia ally no quotations from Sass and Parnas (2007)
simplex” is a “very different diagnostic category” (except a single phrase, and even that turns out
from that of negative-symptom schizophrenia (p. to be inaccurate; on page 87, the phrase used is
565). The concept “negative symptom” is not, not “explanatory power” but “explanatory sig-
however, a diagnostic category at all, but part of nificance”; see Mishara 2007a, 563).
a currently popular way of subtyping symptoms of The first point to be realized is that the Sass
schizophrenia (and some other conditions); nega- and Parnas article from 2007 does not in any way
tive symptoms are typically distinguished from deny the crucial role of neurobiological factors in
positive and disorganization symptoms. the explanation of schizophrenia (nor does Sass
It is obvious, in any case, that “schizophrenia 1992a, which in fact contains a lengthy appendix
simplex,” which lacks both positive and dis- discussing “Neurobiological Considerations”).
organized symptoms, exemplifies at least one, The article focuses, rather, on the distinct yet of-
particularly clear type of the negative syndrome. ten complementary role that an understanding of
Indeed Mishara’s own description of schizophrenia subjectivity can play. The second point is that the
simplex, in the article of his own that he cites here article does not focus primarily on the distinction
(his only relevant citation on the issue; Mishara between understanding and explanation, but on
16  ■  PPP / Vol. 18, No. 1 / March 2011

that between description and explanation. Sass such sequences has “explanatory significance” in
and Parnas (2007) attempt to show that a com- the sense that it clarifies forms of causal or quasi-
monly held view—namely, that phenomenology causal relationship that link one phase to another
is relevant only to description and not to expla- (viz., it is because the visual world has a certain
nation—is inaccurate. It then proceeds to differ- kind of peculiar look—a feature of subjectivity—
entiate a variety of senses of the word “explana- that the patient is motivated to scrutinize what
tion.” The paper explicitly offers a “preliminary is before him, and this in turn leads to certain
taxonomy of six forms of phenomenological consequences). Sass and Parnas take the view
explanation” (p. 67) divided into two groups, that mental patients are conscious human beings;
the first involving a kind of “phenomenological and that, in addition to manifesting the relatively
implication,” the second a kind of “at least quasi- direct consequences of neurobiological abnormali-
causal significance.” The diversity of these modes ties, they will also react to their abnormalities in
of explanation is central to the argument. all kinds of ways that may sometimes require the
The point, then, in Sass and Parnas (2007), categories of meaning and experience in order to
is to show that phenomenological accounts are be understood or explained.
not merely descriptive. But this in no way implies There is something surprisingly mechanistic
that all that is nondescriptive, or “explanatory” about the proposal Mishara (2007a) makes. Al-
in some sense of the latter term, is somehow the though he does not say this in so many words, he
same—as Mishara’s accusation regarding “con- discusses the patient as if he or she were exclusively
flating” would seem to imply. (If A = not-x and B the victim of brain events—as if intentional activ-
= not-x, this does not imply that A = B.) On the ity were irrelevant and subjective experience no
contrary, the whole point of the article is to make it more than epiphenomenal. Mishara’s characteriza-
very clear that not only the general term “explana- tion of natural science as generally “seeking out
tion.” but also the forms of explanation to which explanatory relationships between ever-smaller
phenomenology is relevant. are extremely various, parts” (p. 563) represents a highly reductionistic
ranging from the demonstration of meaningful vision of science that runs counter to mainstream
unities to the clarification of causal sequences and views in both modern and contemporary philoso-
interactions. phy of science (re the latter, see articles in Kendler
In the article, Sass and Parnas (2007) note that and Parnas, 2008)
phenomenology (namely, the description of forms Sass and Parnas do not dispute that neural
of experience or of subjective life) can help to abnormalities play a crucial role, nor indeed that
“explain,” in one sense of that term, by showing, they may often play the most fundamental role
for example, how seemingly distinct features of in terms of kicking off the sequence of events.
conscious experience may actually be mutually “In its most primary form, then, this ‘irritation’
interdependent in the sense of being different as- may well occur in a largely passive manner, and
pects of the same experiential whole (this is called therefore represents an ‘operative’ rather than
a kind of “implicative” relationship). In another ‘reflective’ kind of hyper-reflexivity,” write Sass
sense of the term “explanation,” phenomenology and Parnas (2007, 83; also Sass 1992a, 68–73,
can help one to understand (and also to explain) 374–97). “This ‘irritation’ may, in fact, be a rather
how one form of experience might lead into an- direct consequence of a neurally based cognitive
other, as when unusual features of the subjectively dysfunction.” As examples of the latter dysfunc-
experienced perceptual field (e.g., perceptual frag- tion, Sass and Parnas mention disturbances of
mentation) can inspire or motivate certain forms the hippocampus-based comparator system or of
of (over-focused) attention, which can in turn ‘cognitive coordination’ (citing Gray et al. 1991;
lead to further transformations of the perceptual Phillips and Silverstein, 2003).
field (eventually involving, say, “delusional per- This does not mean, however, that experi-
cept”—as discussed by Matussek, 1987, and also ential phenomena, together with responses to
Sass 1992a, Chapter 2). The understanding of these phenomena, involving different degrees of
Sass, Parnas, and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia  ■  17

volition, may not also play a key role. After all, Indeed, in the article Mishara criticizes, Sass and
even in the case of major physical illnesses, we Parnas (2007, 74–6) explicitly contrast the distinc-
are nearly always confronted with a complex tive explanatory contribution of phenomenology
combination of factors, which include both the with the practical syllogism and the belief-desire
organism’s and the person’s defensive and com- paradigm of mental causation that is commonly
pensatory responses to the originating cause. In proposed in analytic philosophy and that is gener-
the case of psychiatric disorders, these responses ally associated with everyday forms of explana-
are particularly likely to involve reactions (both tion. Sass and Parnas do not deny the relevance of
“consequential” and “compensatory”; Sass and the belief–desire paradigm for explaining certain
Parnas 2007) to lived experiences of various kinds. things. However, they note the problems inherent
Bleuler (1950), who firmly believed in the physical in applying this unadulterated form of everyday
nature of schizophrenia, nevertheless recognized explanation to many apparently irrational actions
the crucial importance of these factors, as can be and beliefs (such as found in schizophrenia); and
seen in his subtle discussion of the precise nature they argue that phenomenological explanation
of the affective disturbance in schizophrenia (see typically directs one’s attention in a different
pp. 40–53, 363–73). Even if something like a direction, namely, “toward formal or structural
neurologically based disorder of attention (see, for features that involve more pervasive aspects or in-
example, Hemsley 2005 for an especially plausible frastructures of human experience (e.g., modes of
account) is primary in a chronological sense, we temporal or spatial experience, general qualities of
are nevertheless presented with a person who, over the object world, forms of self-experience)” (Sass
time, develops a particular cognitive/perceptual and Parnas 2007, 76). As Sass and Parnas say, the
style, way of living, and world perspective—none latter features are typically not part of everyday ex-
of which can be entirely reduced to the attentional planation—which is one reason why psychiatrists
dysfunction itself (Sass 2007b). Understanding and psychologists would do well to be familiar
such styles or perspectives is of obvious relevance with the phenomenological tradition—precisely
for understanding pathogenetic pathways and also to be able to go beyond the resources of everyday
in the therapeutic encounter and for devising new or common-sensical explanation (Gallagher and
forms of psychological intervention. Zahavi 2008; Parnas and Sass 2008; Parnas and
Consideration of possible psychological, Zahavi 2002; Zahavi and Parnas 1998).
meaning-driven sequences is not, incidentally, In several publications, Bovet, Parnas, and Sass
something that can be separated from the search (Bovet and Parnas 1993; Parnas and Sass 2001,
for neurobiological causes. Just one possible 2008; Sass 1990b, 1992a Chapter 9, 1992b,
contribution of the former type of analysis, for 1994, 2004b) have emphasized, for example, the
instance, is that it may help the neuroscientist to relevance of such non-everyday, phenomenological
pare away features that may not be directly related distinctions as Heidegger’s between the “ontologi-
to a malfunctioning or abnormal neural substrate cal” and the “ontic” for the understanding and
(because these features are psychologically ex- explanation of delusions. They have noted, for
plicable) to have a purified understanding of the example, that whereas many paranoid delusions
more direct cognitive or behavioral consequences do imply fairly straightforward forms of “poor re-
of the substrate condition. But it is also true that ality-testing” (the patient believes something false
a predilection for particular modes of attention about a world whose structure is largely analogous
or experience may have its effect on the neuro- to the normal world—“ontic” or “empirical” delu-
biological plane (sometimes termed “downward sions), this is not so clearly the case with some of
causation”). In his discussion, Mishara shows no the more bizarre or metaphysical (“ontological”)
sensitivity to these possibilities. delusions in schizophrenia. Recently Sass (2004b,
It is also simply false to say that Sass and Par- 2007a) has argued that phenomenological notions
nas “opt to associate their phenomenology with about ipseity and the “horizons” of experience
everyday explanation” (Mishara 2007a, 563). can help to explain some of the anomalies of
18  ■  PPP / Vol. 18, No. 1 / March 2011

emotion and affect in schizophrenia (including 4. A more accurate (but impossibly unwieldy) label
certain neurophysiological findings), notably the for the overall model would perhaps be the IHRDSAM,
curious possibility that such patients can experi- standing for the Ipseity/HyperReflexivity/Dimished-Self-
Affection Model.
ence a heightening of certain forms of affectivity
5. Hyper-reflective processes are not always active;
(awe, ontological anxiety) simultaneous with a they can, for example, be quasi-automatized. There are
diminishment of the more passionate or standard many nuances to the activity/passivity issue.
forms of emotionality. 6. More could be said about this topic (self-aware-
ness vs self), but detailed analysis is beyond the scope
of this paper. See Zahavi (2005, 2009).
Conclusion 7. For discussion of how seeking a static, object-like
Overall, Mishara’s arguments in “Missing link” entity precludes finding the self-as-subject, see discussion
betray misunderstanding of the relevant phenom- of William James in chapter 7 of Sass (1992a).
8. Mishara (2007a) misses the relevant point when
enological and psychiatric literature as well as
he acknowledges that, for the IHM, “hyperreflexiv-
failure to grasp the key points of the publications ity (or exaggerated self-reflection) may itself become
he criticizes. In this article, we have addressed most automatic in schizophrenia leading to the ‘pop out’ of
of Mishara’s errors, attempting to do so in a way irrelevant background stimuli and disruptive bottom
that serves the larger purpose of clarifying gen- up processes” (560; also in Mishara 2007b, p. 716n).
eral issues pertaining both to phenomenological Sass and Parnas do indeed mention this latter kind of
psychopathology and to our own perspective on development (which involves an automatizing of reflec-
tion). It would have been more relevant, however, to
schizophrenia. We have concentrated especially on
recognize that, according to our IHM view, operative
several broad points: these include the mutuality of hyperreflexivity is more fundamental, temporally and
the relationship between the phenomenological en- causally, than is hyper-reflection (Sass and Parnas 2007,
terprise and cognitive (neuro)science; the nature of 69, 82–5)—the latter point directly refutes Mishara’s
self-experience—particularly ipseity or pre-reflec- critique.
tive self-consciousness together with the notions 9. Sass (1992a, 228) writes:
of hyperreflexivity and diminished self-affection [The] mode of exigent introspection . . . could also
and their possible disturbance in schizophrenia; reflect some more specific cognitive factor rooted in
the potentially complex interactions of intentional neurobiological abnormalities, such as an incapacity
or quasi-volitional with non-volitional processes (or a disinclination) to synthesize larger Gestalts or,
perhaps, an inability to desist from paying attention to
in the formation of symptomatology; and the pos-
stimuli that are habitually experienced and that would
sible (and diverse) contribution of phenomenology not normally be focused on (kinesthetic and other “in-
to psychological explanation. ner” sensations would be one important subset of such
sensations). In these latter cases, fragmentation of the
Notes self would be not just a consequence but, in a sense, also
1. An additional reason for rejecting Mishara’s use a cause of a certain kind of hyperfocused introspection.
of the term “neophenomenology”: it has already been An attached note cites Hemsley as well as Matussek
used extensively by Herman Schmitz (2003). and Conrad.
2. Mishara himself quotes the phrases “reciprocal 10. The “top down-versus-bottom up” or “from
constraint” and “mutual enlightenment,” even including above-versus-from below” distinction misconstrues
them in the abstract, in Mishara et al. (1998). the difference between Mishara’s and our view, as
3. Sass’s Madness and Modernism (1992a, see pp. explained. Also erroneous is using Nietzsche’s notion
9, 10, 27) is perhaps the most extended recent attempt of the “Dionysian” to describe the view that common
(together with his The Paradoxes of Delusion [1994]) sense fails “because perceptual and automatic meaning
to offer an explicitly hermeneutic-phenomenological processing are [sic] disrupted ‘from below’” (Lysaker
approach to schizophrenia. For introductions to her- and Lysaker 2008a, 32; 2008b, 335, citing Mishara).
meneutic phenomenology’s relevance, see Sass 1988b, In Nietzsche’s Birth of Tragedy, Dionysianism refers to
1998. (In retrospect, Sass would revise his discussion self-dissolution from excess of passion or instinct. This
of Husserl in these latter articles—along lines inspired has nothing in common with the disrupted perceptual/
by Zahavi [2003a] and explained in Thompson [2007, automatic-processing view and seems antithetical to the
appendix A].) nature of schizophrenia (Sass 1992a, Prologue; 2007a).
Sass, Parnas, and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia  ■  19

References Gallagher, S. 1997. Mutual enlightenment: Recent


phenomenology in cognitive science. Journal of
Andreasen, N. C. 2007. DSM and the death of phe-
Consciousness Studies 4:195–214.
nomenology in America: An example of unintended
———. 2003. Phenomenology and experimental
consequences. Schizophrenia Bulletin 33:108–112.
design. Journal of Consciousness Studies 10, no.
Berrios, G. E. 1985. Positive and negative symptoms and
s9–10:85–99.
Jackson. A conceptual history. Archives of General
———. 2005. How the body shapes the mind. Oxford:
Psychiatry 42:95–8.
Oxford University Press.
———. 1991. French views on positive and negative
Gallagher, S., and J. Shear, eds. 1999. Models of the self.
symptoms: A conceptual history. Comprehensive
Thorverton, UK: Imprint Academic.
Psychiatry 32:395–403.
Gallagher, S., and D. Zahavi. 2008. The phenomeno-
Blankenburg, W. 1971. Der Verlust der naturlichen Selb-
logical mind: An introduction to philosophy of mind
stverstandlichkeit: Ein Beitrag zur Psychopathologie
and cognitive science. London: Routledge.
symptomarmer Schizophrenien. Stuttgart: Ferdinand
Gray, J. A., J. Feldon, J. N. Rawlins, D. R. Hemsley, and
Enke Verlag. (The loss of natural self-evidence.)
A. D. Smith. 1991. The neuropsychology of schizo-
———. 1991. La Perte de L’Evidence Naturelle: Une
phrenia. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14:1–20.
Contribution a la Psychopathologie des Schizophré-
Hamilton, M. 1984. Fish’s schizophrenia, 3rd edition.
nies Pauci-Symptomatiques, trans. J.-M. Azorin, and
Bristol: PSG Wright.
Y. Totoyan. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France
Handest, P., and J. Parnas. 2005. Clinical characteristics
(The loss of natural self-evidence.)
of first–admitted patients with ICD-10 schizotypal
Bleuler, E. 1950. Dementia praecox or the group of
disorder. British Journal of Psychiatry 187:s49–s59.
schizophrenias. New York: International Universi-
Heidegger, M. 1989. Die Grundprobleme der Phän-
ties Press.
omenologie. Gesamtausgabe Band 24. Frankfurt am
Bovet, P., and J. Parnas. 1993. Schizophrenic delusions:
Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
A phenomenological approach. Schizophrenia Bul-
———. 1993. Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie
letin 19:579–97.
(1919/1920).Gesamtausgabe Band 58. Frankfurt
Carruthers, P. 1996. Language, thoughts and con-
am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
sciousness. An essay in philosophical psychology.
Hemsley, D. R. 1987. An experimental psychological
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
model for schizophrenia. In Search for the causes of
———. 1998. Natural theories of consciousness. Euro-
schizophrenia, ed. H. Häfner, W. F. Gattaz, and W.
pean Journal of Philosophy 6, no. 2:203–22.
Janzarik. Berlin: Springer.
Chalmers, D. 1995. Facing up to the problem of
———. 1998. Disruption of the “sense of self” in
consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies
schizophrenia: Potential links to disturbances of
2:200–19.
information processing. British Journal of Medical
Chapman, L. J., and J. P. Chapman. 1973. Disordered
Psychology 71:115–24.
thought in schizophrenia. New York: Appleton-
———. 2005. The development of a cognitive model
Century-Crofts.
of schizophrenia: Placing it in context. Neuroscience
Clark, A. 1997. Being there: Putting brain, body, and
and Biobehavioral Reviews 29:977–88.
world together again. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Henry, M. 1963/1973. The essence of manifestation,
Cutting, J. 1997. Principles of psychopathology: Two
trans. G. Etzkorn. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
worlds—two minds—two hemispheres. Oxford, UK:
———. 1975. Philosophy and phenomenology of the
Oxford University Press.
body, trans. G. Etzkorn. The Hague: Nijhoff.
Cutting, J., and F. Dunne. 1989. Subjective experience
Husserl, E. 1950. Cartesianische Meditationen und
of schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Bulletin 15:217–31.
Pariser Vorträge, Husserliana I. Den Haag: Martinus
Cutting, J., and M. Shepherd, eds. 1987. Clinical roots
Nijhoff.
of the schizophrenia concept. Cambridge UK: Cam-
———. 1966a. Zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeit-
bridge University Press.
bewußtseins (1893–1917), Husserliana X.
Dreyfus, H. 1979. What computers can’t do, revised
———. 1966b. Analysen zur passiven Synthesis, Hus-
edition. New York: Harper and Row.
serliana XI. Den Haag: Mar­tinus Nijhoff.
Fuchs, T. 2005. Delusional mood and delusional per-
———. 1973. Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjek-
ception—A phe­nome­nological analysis. Psychopa­
tivität II, Husserliana XIV. Den Haag: Martinus
thology 38:133–9.
Nijhoff.
———. 2007. The temporal structure of intentionality
———. 1982. Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenol-
and its disturbance in schizophrenia. Psychopathol-
ogy and to a phenomenological philosophy: First
ogy 40:229–35.
book, trans. Kersten. Dordrecht, Holland: Kluwer.
20  ■  PPP / Vol. 18, No. 1 / March 2011

———. 1984. Einleitung in die Logik und Erkennt- May, R., E. Angel, and H. Ellenberger. 1958. Existence:
nistheorie, Husserliana XXIV. Den Haag: Martinus A new dimension in psychology and psychiatry. New
Nijhoff. York: Basic Books.
———. 1987/1989. Ideas pertaining to a pure phe- Mayer-Gross, W., E. Slater, and M. Roth. 1954. Clinical
nomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy: psychiatry. London: Cassell.
Second book: Studies in the phenomenology of Merleau-Ponty, M. 1945/1962. The phenomenology of
constitution, trans. R. Rojcewicz, and A. Schuwer. perception, trans. C. Smith. New York: Routledge
Dordrecht, Holland: Kluwer. & Kegan Paul.
Kendler, K., and J. Parnas. eds. 2008. Philosophical Minkowski, E. 1927. La schizophrénie. Paris: Payot.
issues in psychiatry: Explanation, nosology and ———. (1933/2005). Le temps vecu: Etudes phenom-
phenomenology. Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins enologiques et psychopathologiques. Paris: P.U.F.
University Press. Mishara, A. 2001. On Wolfgang Blankenburg, common
Kircher, T., and A. David, eds. 2003. The self in neuro- sense, and schizophrenia. Philosophy, Psychiatry,
science and psychiatry. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Psychology 8:317–22.
University Press. ———. 2004. Disconnection of external and internal
Klosterkötter, J. 1988. Basissymptome und Endphän- in the conscious experience of schizophrenia. Philo-
omene bei Schizophrenia. Berlin: Springer. sophica 73:87–126.
———. 1992. The meaning of basic symptoms for the ———. 2007a. Missing links in phenomenological
development of schizophrenic psychoses. Neurology, clinical neuroscience: Why we still are not there yet.
Psychiatry, and Brain Research 1:30–41. Current Opinion in Psychiatry 20:559–69.
Klosterkötter, J., F. Schultze-Lutter, G. Gross, G. Huber, ———. 2007b. Is minimal self preserved in schizo-
and E. M. Steinmeyer. 1997. Early self-experienced phrenia: A subcomponents view. Consciousness and
neuropsychological deficits and subsequent schizo- Cognition 16:715–21.
phrenic diseases: An 8-year average follow-up Mishara, A., J. Parnas, and J. Naudin. 1998. Forging
prospective study. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica the links between phenomenology, cognitive neuro-
95:396–404.
science and psychopathology. Current Opinion in
Klosterkötter, J., M. Hellmich, E. M. Steinmeyer, and
Psychiatry 3:209–23.
F. Schultze-Lutter. 2001. Diagnosing schizophrenia
Møller, P., and R. Husby. 2000. The initial prodrome
in the initial prodrome phase. Archives of General
in schizophrenia: Searching for naturalistic core di-
Psychiatry 58:158–64.
mensions of experience and behavior. Schizophrenia
Laing, R. D. 1959. The divided self. Harmondsworth,
Bulletin 26:217–32.
UK: Penguin.
Mullen, P. E. 2007. A modest proposal for another
Lewis, M. 2003. The development of self-consciousness.
phenomenological approach to psychopathology.
In Agency and self-awareness, ed. J. Roessler and N.
Schizophrenia Bulletin 33, no. 1:113–21.
Eilan, 275–95. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Nagel, E. 1979. Mortal questions. Cambridge, UK:
Lutz, A. 2002. Toward a neurophenomenology as an
account of generative passages: A first empirical case Cambridge University Press.
study. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Naudin, J. 1997. Phenomenologie et psychiatrie. Tou-
1:133–67. louse, France: Presses Universitaires du Mirail.
Lutz, A., and E. Thompson. 2003. Neurophenomenol- Nelson, B., and L. Sass. 2008. The phenomenology of
ogy: Integrating subjective experience and brain dy- the psychotic break and Huxley’s trip: Substance
namics in the neuroscience of consciousness. Journal use and the onset of psychosis. Psychopathology
of Consciousness Studies 10:31–52. 41:346–55.
Lysaker, P. H., and J. T. Lysaker. 2008a. Schizophrenia Nelson, B., L. A. Sass, and B. Skodlar. 2009. The phe-
and the fate of the self. Oxford UK: Oxford Uni- nomenological model of psychotic vulnerability and
versity Press. its possible implications for psychological interven-
———. 2008b. Schizophrenia and alterations in self tions in the ultra-high risk (prodromal) population.
experience: A comparison of six perspectives. Schizo- Psychopathology 42:283–92.
phrenia Bulletin 36, no. 2:331–40. Nelson, B., L. A. Sass, A. Thompson, A. R. Yung, S.
Maj, M. 2005. “Psychiatric comorbidity”: An artefact M. Francey, G. P. Amminger, and P. D. McGorry.
of current diagnostic systems? British Journal of 2009. Does disturbance of self underlie social cog-
Psychiatry 186:182–4. nition deficits in schizophrenia and other psychotic
Matussek, P. 1987. Studies in delusional perception. In disorders? Early Intervention in Psychiatry 3:83–93.
The clinical roots of the schizophrenia concept, ed. Nelson, B., A. R. Yung, A. Bechdolf, and P. D. McGorry.
J. Cutting and M. Shepherd, 89–103. Cambridge: 2008. The phenomenological critique and self-distur-
Cambridge University Press.
Sass, Parnas, and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia  ■  21

bance: Implications for ultra-high risk (‘prodrome’) Parnas, J., and D. Zahavi. 2002. The role of phenom-
research. Schizophrenia Bulletin 34:381–92. enology in psychiatric classification and diagnosis.
Parnas, J. 2003. Self and schizophrenia: A phenomeno- In: Psychiatric diagnosis and classification (World
logical perspective. In The self in neuroscience and Psychiatric Association Series), ed. M. Maj, W.
psychiatry, ed. T. Kircher and A. David, 217–41. Gaebel, J. J. Lopez-Ibor, and N. Sartorius, 137–62.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. New York: John Wiley & Sons.
———. 2005. Clinical detection of schizophrenia-prone Phillips, W. A., and S. M. Silverstein. 2003. Convergence
individuals: Critical appraisal. British Journal of of biological and psychological perspectives on cog-
Psychiatry 187:s111–s112. nitive coordination in schizophrenia. Behavioral and
Parnas, J., and P. Bovet. 1991. Autism in schizophrenia Brain Sciences 26:65–82.
revisited. Comprehensive Psychiatry 32:7–21. Ratcliffe, M. 2008. Feelings of being: Phenomenology,
Parnas J., P. Bovet, and G. Innocenti. 1996. Schizo- psychiatry, and the sense of reality. Oxford, UK:
phrenic trait features, binding and cortico-cortical Oxford University Press.
connectivity: a neurodevelopmental pathogenetic Ricoeur, P. 1966. Freedom and nature: The voluntary
hypothesis. Neurology, Psychiatry and Brain Re- and the involuntary. Evanston, IL: Northwestern
search 4:185–96. University Press.
Parnas J., P. Bovet, and D. Zahavi. 2002. Schizophrenic ———. 1992. Oneself as another, trans. K. Blamey.
autism: Clinical phenomenology and pathogenetic Chicago: University Chicago Press.
implications. World Psychiatry 1/3:131–6. Rulf, S. 2003. Phenomenological contributions on
Parnas, J. and P. Handest. 2003. Phenomenology of schizophrenia: A critical review and commentary
anomalous self-experience in early schizophrenia. on the literature between 1980–2000. Journal of
Comprehensive Psychiatry 44:121–34. Phenomenological Psychology 34, no. 1:1–46.
Parnas, J., P. Handest, L. Jansson, and D. Sæbye. 2005. Sartre, J. P. 1956. Being and nothingness, trans. H. E.
Anomalous subjective experience among first ad- Barnes. New York: Philosophical Library.
Sass, L. l985. Time, space, and symbol: A study of narra-
mitted schizophrenia spectrum patients: Empirical
tive form and representational structure in madness
investigation. Psychopathology 38, no. 5:259–67.
and modernism. Psychoanalysis and Contemporary
Parnas J, P. Handest, D. Sæbye, and L. Jansson. 2003.
Thought 8:45–85.
Anomalies of subjective experience in schizophre-
———. l987. Introspection, schizophrenia, and the
nia and psychotic bipolar illness. Acta Psychiatrica
fragmentation of self. Representations 19:l–34.
Scandinavica 108:126–33.
———. l988a. The land of unreality: On the phenom-
Parnas, J., L. Jansson, L. A. Sass, and P. Handest. 1998.
enology of the schizophrenic break. New Ideas in
Self-experience in the prodromal phases of schizo-
Psychology 6:223–42.
phrenia: A pilot study of first admissions. Neurology,
———. l988b. Humanism, hermeneutics, and the
Psychiatry, and Brain Research 6:107–16.
concept of the human subject. In Hermeneutics and
Parnas J., P. Møller, T. Kircher, J. Thalbitzer, L. Jansson, psychological theory, ed. S. Messer, L. Sass, and R.
P. Handest, and D. Zahavi. 2005. EASE: Examina- Woolfolk, 222–71. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers
tion of Anomalous Self-experience. Psychopathology University Press.
38, no. 5:236–58. ———. 1990a. The truth‑taking stare: A Heideggerian
Parnas, J., and L. Sass. 2001. Self, solipsism, and interpretation of a schizophrenic world. Journal of
schizophrenic delusions. Philosophy, Psychiatry, Phenomenological Psychology 21:121–49.
Psychology 8:101–20. ———. 1990b. On delusions. Raritan 9:120–41.
———. 2008. Varieties of “phenomenology”: On ———. 1992a. Madness and modernism: Insanity in
description, understanding, and explanation in the light of modern art, literature, and thought. New
psychiatry. In Philosophical issues in psychiatry: York: Basic Books. (Harvard paperback 1994.)
Explanation, nosology and phenomenology, ed. K. ———. 1992b. Heidegger, schizophrenia, and the
Kendler and J. Parnas, 239–78. Baltimore, MD: The ontological difference. Philosophical Psychology
Johns Hopkins University Press. 5:109–32.
Parnas, J., L. Sass, and D. Zahavi. 2008. Recent develop- ———. 1994. The Paradoxes of delusion: Wittgenstein,
ments in philosophy and psychopathology. Current Schreber, and the schizophrenic mind. Ithaca, NY:
Opinion in Psychiatry 21, no. 6:578–84. Cornell University Press.
Parnas, J., P. Vianin, D. Sæbye, L. Jansson, A. V. Larsen, ———. 1998. “Ambiguity is of the essence”: The
and P. Bovet. 2001. Visual binding abilities in the relevance of hermeneutics for psychoanalysis. In
initial and advanced stages of schizophrenia. Acta Psychoanalytic versions of the human condition and
Psychiatrica Scand 103:171–80. clinical practice, ed. P. Marcus, and A. Rosenberg,
257–305. New York: New York University Press.
22  ■  PPP / Vol. 18, No. 1 / March 2011

———. 2000. Schizophrenia, self-experience, and the Schwartz, M. A., and O. P. Wiggins. 1987. Typifications.
so-called “negative symptoms.” In Exploring the self: The first step for clinical diagnosis in psychiatry.
Philosophical and psychopathological perspectives Journal of Nervous and Mental Diseases 175:65–77.
on self-experience, ed. D. Zahavi, 149–82. Amster- Schwartz, M. A., O. P. Wiggins, J. Naudin, and M.
dam & Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Co. Spitzer. 2005. Rebuilding reality: A phenomenology
———, ed. 2001a. The phenomenology of schizophre- of aspects of chronic schizophrenia. Phenomenology
nia: Three classic approaches. Philosophy, Psychia- and the Cognitive Sciences 4:91–115.
try, & Psychology 8 no. 4:special issue. Skodlar, B., M. Tomori, and J. Parnas. 2008. Subjective
———. 2001b. Self and world in schizophrenia: Three experience and suicidal ideation in schizophrenia.
classic approaches. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psy- Comprehensive Psychiatry 49, no. 5:482–8 E.
chology 8, no. 4:251–70. Spitzer, M. 1988. Ichstörungen: In search of a theory. In
———. 2003a. “Negative symptoms, schizophrenia, Psychopathology and philosophy, ed. M. Spitzer, F.
and the self. International Journal of Psychology and A. Uehlein, and G. Oepen, 167–83. Berlin: Springer.
Psychological Therapy 3:153–80. (available from: Stanghellini, G. 2001. Psychopathology of common
http://www.ijpsy.com/volumen3/num2/62.html) sense. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 8, no.
———. 2003b. Schizophrenia and the self: Hyperre- 2/3:201–18.
flexivity and diminished self-affection. In The Self in ———. 2004. Disembodied spirits and deanimated bod-
schizophrenia: Neuropsychological perspectives, ed. ies: The psychopathology of common sense. Oxford,
T. Kircher and A. David. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge UK: Oxford University Press.
University Press. Stangehellini, G., and M. Ballerini. 2007. Values in
———. 2004a. “Negative symptoms,” commonsense, persons with schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Bulletin
and cultural disembedding in the modern age. In 33, no. 1:131–41.
Schizophrenia, Culture, and subjectivity: The edge Tatossian, A. 1979. La phénomenologie des psychoses.
of experience, ed. J. Jenkins, and R. Barrett, 303–28. Paris: Masson, 1979. (reprinted, Paris: L’Art du
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Comprendre, 1997).
———. 2004b. Affectivity in schizophrenia: A phenom- Thompson, E. 2007. Mind in life: Biology, phenom-
enological perspective. Journal of Consciousness enology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge, MA:
Studies 11:127–47. Harvard University Press.
———. 2004c. Schizophrenia: A disturbance of the Uhlhaas, P. J., and A. Mishara. 2007. Perceptual anoma-
thematic field. In Gurwitsch’s relevancy for the cogni- lies in schizophrenia: Integrating phenomenology
tive sciences, ed. L. Embree, 59–78. Dordrecht, The and cognitive neuroscience. Schizophrenia Bulletin
Netherlands: Springer. 33, no. 1:142–56.
———. 2007a. Contradictions of emotion in schizo- Varela, F. 1996. Neurophenomenology. Journal of
phrenia. Cognition and Emotion 21:351–90. Consciousness Studies 3:330–49.
———. 2007b. “Person with schizophrenia” or “schizo- Varela, F. J., E. Thompson, and E. Rosch. 1991. The
phrenic person”: Reflections on illness and the self. embodied mind: Cognitive science and human ex-
Theory and Psychology 17:395–420. perience. Cambridge: MIT Press.
———. 2011. Autonomy and schizophrenia: Reflections Vollmer-Larsen, A. 2008. The course and outcome in
on an ideal. In Personality and psychopathology: schizophrenia spectrum disorders: A 5-year follow-
Critical dialogues with David Shapiro, ed. C. Piers, up in Copenhagen prodromal study. University of
99–131. New York: Springer. Copenhagen: PhD dissertation.
Sass, L., and J. Parnas. 2003. Schizophrenia, conscious- Vollmer-Larsen, A., P. Handest, and J. Parnas. 2007.
ness, and the self. Schizophrenia Bulletin 29:427–44. Reliability of measuring anomalous experience: The
———. 2007. Explaining schizophrenia: The relevance Bonn scale for the assessment of basic symptoms.
of phenomenology. In Reconceiving schizophrenia, Psychopathology 345–8.
ed. M. C. Chung, K. W. M. Fulford, and G. Graham, Wiggins, O. P., M. A. Schwartz, and G. Northoff. 1990.
63–95. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Toward a Husserlian phenomenology of the initial
Sass, L., J. Whiting, and J. Parnas. 2000. Mind, self, stages of schizophrenia. In Philosophy and psycho-
and psychopathology: Reflections on philosophy, pathology, ed. M. Spitzer, and B. Maher, 21–34.
theory, and the study of mental illness. Theory and Berlin, Springer-Verlag.
Psychology 10:87–98. Zahavi, D. 1999. Self-awareness and alterity: A phe-
Schmitz, H. 2003. Was ist neue phänomenologie? Ros- nomenological investigation. Evanston, IL: North-
tock: Koch Verlag. western University Press.
Sass, Parnas, and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia  ■  23

———. 2003a. Husserl’s phenomenology. Stanford: ———. 2005. Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating
Stanford University Press. the first-person perspective. Cambridge MA: MIT
———. 2003b. Inner time-consciousness and pre- Press.
reflective selfawareness. In The new Husserl: A ———. 2009. Is the self a social construct? Inquiry 52,
critical reader, ed. D. Welton, 157–80. Bloomington: no. 6:551–73.
Indiana University Press. Zahavi, D., and J. Parnas. 1998. Phenomenal con-
———. 2004. Phenomenology and the project of sciousness and self-awareness. A phenomenologi-
naturalization. Phenomenology and the Cognitive cal critique of representational theory. Journal of
Sciences 3:331–47. Consciousness Studies 5/5–6:687–705.

View publication stats

Вам также может понравиться