Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 15

ANGEL AK I

journal of the theoretical humanities


volume 11 number 3 december 2006

Deleuze, philosopher, son of Diogenes and


Hypatia, sojourned at Lyon. Nothing is known
of his life. He lived to be very old, even though
he was often very ill. This illustrated what he
himself had said: there are lives in which the
difficulties verge on the prodigious. He
defined as active any force that goes to the
end of its power. This, he said, is the opposite
of a law. Thus he lived, always going further
than he had believed he could. Even though he
had explicated Chrysippus, it is above all his
steadfastness that earned him the name of
Stoic.1
john sellars
his is the opening paragraph of André
T Bernold’s tribute to Gilles Deleuze, entitled
‘‘Suidas,’’ and published a few months after
Deleuze’s death in 1995. Modelled on the ancient
philosophical biographies that one finds in the AN ETHICS OF THE
pages of the ninth-century Byzantine encyclope- EVENT
dia Suidas and in the Lives and Opinions of the
Philosophers by Diogenes Laertius, it presents deleuze’s stoicism
Deleuze as if he were an ancient philosopher. In
particular, it presents Deleuze as a philosopher
in a genealogy of Cynics (‘‘son of Diogenes’’) and outside the category of ‘‘being’’ but within the
Stoics (‘‘explicated Chrysippus’’). As it con- broader category of ‘‘something.’’3 This concern
tinues, Bernold’s tribute emphasizes that with the ontological status of sense is the
Deleuze ‘‘must be placed in the ranks of the principal reason why Deleuze turns to the
physicists,’’ alongside Heraclitus and Lucretius. Stoics, but his engagement with Stoicism in
Bernold’s text paints a portrait of Deleuze – The Logic of Sense is by no means confined to
supposedly the arch ‘‘post-structuralist’’ – that is their theory of incorporeals. He also explores
thoroughly pre-modern. their conception of time, which he presents as a
Anyone familiar with Deleuze’s œuvre as a twofold theory of aiôn and chronos,4 as well as
whole will know that in his 1969 book The Logic Stoic ethics and the Stoic ‘‘image of the
of Sense, there is an extended engagement with philosopher.’’5 One might say that Deleuze’s
ancient Stoicism.2 Deleuze’s project in The Logic principal theme of the logic (or ontology) of sense
of Sense is to give an account of linguistic provides him with a way into a much broader
meaning or sense as a non-existing entity, and exploration of ancient Stoicism.
in order to do this he draws upon the Stoic theory Broad as Deleuze’s engagement with Stoicism
of incorporeals, in which linguistic meaning is in The Logic of Sense might be, on its own
classified as one of four incorporeal entities it hardly seems enough to justify Bernold’s
ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN1469-2899 online/06/030157^15 ß 2006 Taylor & Francis and the Editors of Angelaki
DOI: 10.1080/09697250601048622

157
deleuze’s stoicism

characterization of Deleuze as a Stoic. After all, affinity with Anglo-American philosophers such
Stoicism forms just one of a number of sources in as Whitehead, James, and even Bertrand
just one of Deleuze’s books, which number more Russell.10 One can also see why he was drawn
than twenty in all. According to Bernold, to the empiricist Stoics who were among the first
however, ‘‘even though he had explicated to reject Platonic metaphysics. Indeed, one of
Chrysippus, it is above all his steadfastness Deleuze’s principal reasons for turning to the
(constance) that earned him the name of Stoic.’’ Stoics was because, he suggests, they were the
In other words, it is not Deleuze’s explicit first to have ‘‘reversed Platonism,’’ a task that
discussion of Stoicism in The Logic of Sense Deleuze says is the task for all modern
that makes him a Stoic for Bernold; it is philosophy, or at the very least his own.11 As
something else, something deeper within his such, the Stoics stand at the beginning of a
overall philosophical outlook. tradition of immanence within Western philoso-
This deeper affinity with Stoicism can be phy that runs from them through Spinoza and
found throughout Deleuze’s œuvre, although Nietzsche to Deleuze himself.12 The Stoic reversal
many of the seeds can be found in The Logic of Platonism involves switching the ontological
of Sense.6 For him, the Stoics stand alongside order of priority between ideas and matter. For
Spinoza, Nietzsche, Bergson, and others who Plato, ideas have ontological priority while the
form an alternative to the dominant figures from world of appearances is merely in a state of
the history of philosophy whom he had encoun- becoming. For the Stoics, by contrast, only
tered (such as Plato, Descartes, and Kant). In material bodies exist. The contents of ideas are
short, Deleuze rejected the rationalist tradition reduced to mere incorporeal effects in the form of
that he was taught and embraced what he took to what the Stoics call lekta or ‘‘sayables,’’ while
be an alternative empiricist tradition. In the universal concepts are dismissed as not even this,
Preface to the English edition of Dialogues, he being figments of the imagination on a par with
writes: dreams and hallucinations. ‘‘The Idea again falls
to the surface as a simple incorporeal effect’’ (LS
In so-called rationalist philosophies, the 157/132). The Stoics reject the Platonic heights
abstract is given the task of explaining, and of transcendence and also the Presocratic idea of
it is the abstract that is realized in the
hidden depths in nature. Instead, everything that
concrete. One starts with abstractions such as
exists does so on the surface that is nature,
the One, the Whole, the Subject, and one
looks for the process by which they are Deleuze suggests:
embodied in a world which they make
With the Megarians, Cynics, and Stoics, we
conform to their requirements.7
have the beginning of a new philosopher and
a new kind of anecdote. [. . .] This is a
In contrast to this, ultimately Platonic, tradition
reorientation of all thought and of what it
in philosophy, Deleuze presents himself as an
means to think: there is no longer depth or
empiricist, adopting Whitehead’s definition of height. (LS 155/129–30)
empiricism: the abstract does not explain any-
thing but must itself be explained.8 For Deleuze, As this passage indicates, Deleuze connects
this empiricism rejects abstract totalities and Stoic immanent ontology with a new image of the
unities, affirming instead the ontological priority philosopher as a creature of the surface, for whom
of pluralities and multiplicities, and insisting thought and life are united as one,13 an image
upon the externality of relations. As William that Deleuze develops into his concept of
James put it, ‘‘Empiricism [. . .] lays the ‘‘practical philosophy.’’14 Notwithstanding his
explanatory stress upon the part, the element, explicit definition of philosophy as the ‘‘creation
the individual, and treats the whole as a collection of concepts,’’ in a number of places Deleuze
and the universal as an abstraction.’’9 With this gestures towards a practical conception of
in mind, one can see why Deleuze chose to devote philosophy that shares much with this Stoic
his first book to Hume and why he felt a certain image of the philosopher. In a discussion from

158
sellars

1972 entitled ‘‘Intellectuals and Power,’’ Deleuze Marcus Aurelius.19 How might one, they ask,
and Foucault consider the relationship between replicate the escape from the self embodied by
theory and practice.15 Deleuze suggests that in the schizophrenic or the drug user without falling
the past, practice has been conceived either as the into complete self-destruction. Might it be
application of theory (coming after theory) or as possible, they ask, to replicate the experiences
the inspiration for theory (coming before theory), of the schizophrenic or the drug user without
and here he is primarily thinking in terms of going mad or becoming an addict, ‘‘to get drunk
political theory and its relationship with political on pure water, as in Henry Miller’s experimenta-
activism. He goes on to suggest that ‘‘for us’’ – tions’’ (MP 204/166)? Deleuze raises this same
for Deleuze and Foucault, and perhaps others of question in The Logic of Sense, where he
their generation – the relationship between theory wonders whether it might be possible to recover
and practice is no longer so linear (whether it be the effects of drugs and alcohol independently of
theory leading to practice or practice leading to the use of those substances (see LS 188–89/161).
theory). Instead, ‘‘Practice is a set of relays from With this in mind, he suggests becoming a little
one theoretical point to another, and theory is a crazy or a little alcoholic, ‘‘just enough to extend
relay from one practice to another.’’16 Indeed, the crack, but not enough to deepen it irreme-
they go on to argue that theory is itself a form of diably’’ (LS 184/157–8). Deleuze wonders just
practice – theoretical action stands alongside how this might be attained. He responds to this
practical action, and both join together in question of his with the words ‘‘How much we
networks of relays. A theory is, says Deleuze, have yet to learn from Stoicism . . .’’ (LS 184/
like a box of tools, and as such must be useful and 158). Here, in The Logic of Sense, Deleuze rather
must work. Furthermore, ‘‘If no one uses it, enigmatically implies that his project of recover-
beginning with the theoretician himself (who then ing the experiences of the drug user without
ceases to be a theoretician), then the theory is drugs, of extending the crack in the self without
worthless or the moment is inappropriate.’’17 The cracking up, that dominates his later work with
position that Deleuze outlines in this discussion Guattari has already been accomplished in
bears some striking resemblance to the Stoic Stoicism.
conception of philosophy. Philosophy proper is We also find in A Thousand Plateaus an
not merely philosophical theory or discourse; analysis of the politics of space that echoes Stoic
instead, philosophy is a lived practice that is built cosmopolitanism. According to Plutarch, Stoic
upon both philosophical theory and practical cosmpolitanism – in which the wise conceive
exercises. Of course, Deleuze does not equate the themselves as citizens distributed across an
practices that he is discussing with the sort of undivided Cosmos, indifferent to traditional
philosophical training outlined by the Stoics; the States – was inspired by a reference in Zeno’s
parallel is at the level of the relationship between now lost Republic exhorting all humankind to
theory and philosophy itself as a practice. What live as if grazing on a common pasture (nomos).
Deleuze and the Stoics share in common here is For the Stoics, territory should not be divided
the thought that philosophical discourse is but up among individuals; instead, individuals should
one part of a broader practical conception of scatter themselves across an undivided space.
philosophy.18 The aim of philosophy in both This pre-empts Deleuze’s own account of differ-
cases is a transformation of one’s mode of ing modes of distribution in Difference and
existence or way of life. Repetition, which forms the basis for the
Resonances with Stoicism can also be found in ‘‘nomadology’’ of A Thousand Plateaus.20
Deleuze’s collaborative work with Félix Guattari, As well as all of these resonances between
especially A Thousand Plateaus. In this work, Deleuze’s philosophy and Stoicism, Deleuze also
we find a philosophical project aimed at calling goes so far as to suggest that today the Stoics
into question the rigid boundaries between the offer us the only meaningful form of ethics left –
self and cosmos that is a striking echo of the not to be unworthy of what happens to us – and
project laid out in the Meditations of he connects this with Nietzsche’s amor fati.

159
deleuze’s stoicism

In what follows, I shall focus my attention on this instance, in the attempt by Marcus Aurelius to
last Stoic theme within Deleuze’s philosophy, develop a cosmic perspective.23 The logical pole,
namely his conception of an ethics of the event, on the other hand, is concerned with the use of
considering this alongside Bernold’s attribution representations,24 and it is this pole that Deleuze
to Deleuze of a Stoic ‘‘steadfastness’’ (constance). associates with ‘‘willing the event whatever it may
I shall begin (in sect. I) with Deleuze’s account be’’ (LS 169/144). These two poles of Stoic ethics
of Stoic ethics in The Logic of Sense and the are mapped onto the two sides of Stoic ontology:
connections he makes with Nietzschean amor the physical pole is concerned with corporeal
fati. Then (in sect. II) I shall compare this with causes while the logical pole is concerned with
the popular image of Stoicism as a philosophy of incorporeal events.
heroic endurance or steadfastness, offering a The logical pole of Stoic ethics concerned with
genealogical account of the origins of this willing the event involves, according to
image. By returning to the works of the late Goldschmidt, accepting that which occurs
Stoic philosophers (in sect. III) I shall try to (accepter ce qui arrive) – an active acceptance
account for the existence of these two apparently that implies a welcome cooperation with fate.25
conflicting images of Stoicism and then try to Goldschmidt cites the Stoic Epictetus:
reconcile them. By way of conclusion (in sect. IV)
I shall outline the Stoic character of Deleuze’s The philosophers are right to say that if a wise
and good man had foreknowledge of events, he
ethics and then, finally (in sect. V), assess
would work to assist nature even when it
Bernold’s presentation of Deleuze as a steadfast comes to sickness and death and mutilation,
Stoic. being aware that these things are allotted in
accordance with the ordering of the universe.26
I deleuze’s stoics Moreover, to complain about what comes to pass
It is in the twentieth and twenty-first series of corrupts the perfection of the cosmos, according
The Logic of Sense that we find Deleuze’s explicit to Marcus Aurelius:
discussion of Stoic ethics. First and foremost,
Stoic ethics is an immanent ethics built upon the There are thus two reasons why you should
be contented with whatever befalls you, firstly,
materialism of Stoic physics. Virtue and vice are
that it was for you that it came about, and it
themselves bodies if they are to play any causal was prescribed for you and stands in a special
role in actions. Good and bad encounters are relationship to you as something that was spun
mixtures or interactions of bodies that are good into your destiny from the beginning and
or bad from the perspective of a particular body issues from the most venerable of causes, and
but not from the perspective of the cosmos as a secondly, that for the power which governs
whole. For Deleuze, the principal lesson of Stoic the whole, that which comes to each of us
ethics is to affirm all such encounters: ‘‘Stoic individually contributes to its own well-being
ethics is concerned with the event; it consists of and perfection and its very continuance. For
willing (vouloir) the event as such, that is, of the perfection of the whole suffers a mutilation
if you cut off even the smallest particle from
willing that which occurs (vouloir ce qui arrive)
the coherence and continuity of its causes no
insofar as it does occur’’ (LS 168/143).
less than of its parts; and you break it off, so
According to Deleuze, who here follows the far as you can, whenever you are discontented,
work of Victor Goldschmidt,21 there are two and, in a certain sense, you destroy it.27
poles within Stoic ethics relating to its relation-
ships with the two other parts of Stoic philoso- Thus, it is necessary to bring one’s own will into
phy: physics and logic. The physical pole of Stoic harmony with the will of fate. The event that
ethics is concerned with the continuum of causes/ must be affirmed is ‘‘already in the process of
bodies that constitute the cosmos.22 It is a being produced by and in the depth of corporeal
question of situating oneself within the order of causes’’ (LS 172/147), and consequently there is a
causes. This pole of Stoic ethics can be seen, for sense in which the event is determined before it

160
sellars

comes to pass. The Stoic sage must will the The two poles of Stoic ethics – the physical
embodiment of a pre-existing event. It is within and the logical – are said to correlate with two
this context that Deleuze cites a line from Joë distinct conceptions of time.34 Deleuze labels
Bousquet as a Stoic maxim: ‘‘my wound existed these two conceptions of time aiôn and chronos,
before me, I was born to embody it’’ (LS 174/ and attributes them to the Stoics, although it may
148).28 Bousquet, paralysed by a war wound aged be more accurate to say that they derive from
20 and bedridden for the rest of his life, tried ‘‘to Goldschmidt’s reading of the Stoics.35 Rather
reduce himself entirely to events,’’29 holding that than conceive time as a continuum divided into
only events are real and that our task is to assist the three parts of past, present, and future,
in their realization.30 Bousquet’s maxim is a Deleuze suggests that the Stoics separated the
striking echo of Marcus Aurelius’s ‘‘it was for you present from the past and future. On the one
that it came about, and it was prescribed for you hand the Stoics conceived time as chronos,
and stands in a special relationship to you as the extended, but limited, living present. On
something that was spun into your destiny from the other hand they conceived time as aiôn, the
the beginning.’’ unlimited past and future. Under chronos, the
Deleuze goes on to associate this Stoic (and present moment has a certain extension or
Bousquetian) ethic of willing the event with duration (étendue ou durée), an extension that
Nietzsche’s amor fati.31 In an emphatic claim, he can expand or contract – the present discussion,
says, ‘‘Either ethics makes no sense at all, or this the present day, the present year. It can even
is what it means and has nothing else to say: not expand to encompass all of time, becoming the
to be unworthy of what happens to us’’ (LS 174/ cosmic present. From the perspective of chronos,
149). One faces two alternatives: either to the past and future are merely parts of some
embrace the event, whatever it may bring, or to larger present that subsumes the current present;
despise the event as something unpleasant and there exists a series of presents of differing
unjust. In Nietzschean terms, this is the choice extensions enveloping one another, all ultimately
between amor fati and ressentiment. For Deleuze, enveloped by the cosmic present. If one has not
reached the cosmic present, however, from the
the only meaningful ethical response is to affirm
perspective of a narrower present, ‘‘there are
that which comes to pass, to will it as if it were
many injustices and ignominies, many parasitic
what we would have chosen for ourselves. As
and cannibalistic processes which inspire our
Bousquet said, with regard to his paralysing
terror at what happens to us, and our resentment
wound, ‘‘I put all my strength into naturalizing
at what occurs’’ (LS 177/151). In order to escape
the accident that victimized my youth. I wanted
ressentiment, then, we must cultivate the all-
it to cease to be outside me.’’32 The task for
encompassing cosmic present.
Bousquet was to transform the event of the Under aiôn, the relationship between the
wound from a tragic external assault that afflicted present on the one hand and the past and
him into a vital and necessary event in his life future on the other is reversed. Instead of a
that made it possible for him to discover himself present that can expand and absorb the past and
as a writer, to become who he already was. For an future, under aiôn the extended present evapo-
individual conceived as a unified, static object, rates in a process of subdivision into part of the
events are external assaults that threaten one’s past and part of the future. The extended present
current existence; for an individual conceived is replaced by the instant, a mathematical limit
as a process or series of events, by contrast, every without thickness or extension that stands
new event becomes a constitutive component that between past and future.
must be affirmed as part of oneself. In contrast to From the perspective of the cosmic present of
this ethics of the event, what would be really chronos – the eternal or divine present – all of
immoral, Deleuze suggests, would be to apply time can be encompassed, and each event can be
moral concepts such as just or unjust, merit or situated within the series of physical mixtures
fault, to events (‘‘the world is unfair’’).33 that constitute the whole: this relates to the

161
deleuze’s stoicism

physical pole of Stoic ethics. From the perspec- evils, Lipsius should turn his attention inward
tive of aiôn, however, each event is understood and examine his own thoughts and emotions. The
only as a bridge between the immediate past and solution to public evils, Langius implies, is to be
immediate future, and Deleuze characterizes this found in ethical psychotherapy rather than in
as an incorporeal transformation, related to the travel or politics. The public evils that Lipsius
logical pole of Stoic ethics. As we shall see, both hopes to flee are, Langius continues, the product
poles play a part in Deleuze’s Stoic ethics. of ‘‘the smoke of opinions’’ for which the cure
is not travel but reason. Langius develops his
argument in a number of ways, building upon
II amor fati versus heroic endurance
two claims. The first is that if travelling were the
Deleuze’s presentation of Stoic ethics as a way to escape pubic evils, then it would require
precursor to Nietzsche’s amor fati shares little travelling to a place completely free from such
in common with the popular conception of evils; such a place does not exist. The second is
Stoicism as an attitude of heroic endurance in that even if such a place did exist, settling there
the face of adversity. In the popular image, the would offer no respite for the troubles afflicting
Stoic is one who nobly endures the evils thrown at Lipsius, for those troubles are ultimately the
him by a hostile world. The Oxford English product of his own mind. Public evils are,
Dictionary, for example, defines a Stoic as ‘‘one Langius argues, internal rather than external. As
who practises repression of emotion, indifference such, travelling can never free us from them; only
to pleasure or pain, and patient endurance.’’36 reason can cure Lipsius from the public evils that
The origins of this modern popular image of the he is trying to escape. Langius quotes an anecdote
Stoic can be traced back to the sixteenth century. attributed to Socrates from Seneca’s Letters:
In 1584, the Belgian Humanist Justus Lipsius ‘‘How can you wonder your travels do you no
published De Constantia, a work in which he good, when you carry yourself around with
proposed Stoicism as an antidote to public evils – you?’’40
in particular, the civil and religious wars afflicting With these claims, the Stoic flavour of the
northern Europe.37 The book proved to be work as a whole is made clear. For Langius, the
especially popular and was translated into source of all human misery is internal rather than
numerous vernacular languages before the end external. Once we realize the true location of the
of the sixteenth century and reprinted throughout source of our suffering, not only are we a step
the seventeenth century,38 while in the eighteenth closer to being able to cure it, but also
century, Lipsius is cited by Diderot as the we suddenly realize that it is something that is
principal modern reviver of Stoicism.39 It is in ‘‘up to us’’ (eph’ hêmin). As the Stoic Epictetus
De Constantia that we find Stoicism presented put it:
as a philosophy of heroic endurance in the face of
adversity. Some things are up to us, while others are not
Lipsius’s De Constantia takes the form of a up to us. Up to us are conception, choice,
dialogue between Lipsius and his elder mentor desire, aversion, and, in a word, everything
Langius, and is set within the context of a trip to that is our own doing; not up to us are our
Vienna actually undertaken by Lipsius in 1572. body, our property, reputation, office, and, in
In the opening monologue, Lipsius recounts that a word, everything that is not our own doing.
Furthermore, the things up to us are by nature
the principal motivation for his trip was to escape
free, unhindered, and unimpeded; while the
the public evils (mala publica) plaguing his
things not up to us are weak, servile, subject to
homeland Belgium. Langius’s opening contribu- hindrance, and not our own. Remember,
tion to the dialogue immediately sets the tone for therefore, that if what is naturally slavish
the remainder of the work: Lipsius is mistaken, you think to be free, and what is not your own
Langius says, in thinking that fleeing troubles to be your own, you will be hampered, will
in Belgium will enable him to escape troubles grieve, will be in turmoil, and will blame both
completely; rather than run away from public gods and men; while if you think only what is

162
sellars
your own to be your own, and what is not your one will meet grief and sickness. These cannot be
own to be, as it really is, not your own, then no avoided but they can be despised (effugere ista
one will ever be able to exert compulsion upon non potes, contemnere potes).47 The task is to
you, no one will hinder you, you will blame no prepare oneself to meet such evils, for once
one, will find fault with no one, will do
prepared one will be able to meet them
absolutely nothing against your will, you will
have no personal enemy, no one will harm
courageously (fortius). Thus, one should engage
you, for neither is there any harm that can in a continual reflection upon future evils so that
touch you.41 when they come – as they surely will – one will be
ready. As Seneca puts it: ‘‘It is not possible to
The antidote to public evils is, of course, change this condition of things; but it is possible
constancy (constantia). Constancy is defined as to take on a noble soul worthy of a good man,
‘‘a right and immovable strength of mind, neither thereby courageously enduring chance (fortiter
lifted up nor pressed down with external or causal fortuita patiamur) and being in harmony with
accidents.’’42 It is an attitude of indifference to nature.’’48
externals precisely of the sort proposed by The task at hand, then, is to transform one’s
Epictetus.43 This strength of mind is built upon soul in order to bring it into harmony with the
rational judgement, in contrast to inconstancy, law of Nature, which it should follow and obey
which is the product of mere opinion. (hanc sequatur, huic pareat).49 We should,
Langius presents the battle between reason and Seneca suggests, follow the will of God without
opinion as a battle between the soul and the body: complaint, under which everything progresses.
constancy will arise in a rational life directed Rather than go against the divine order of the
by the soul, unperturbed by the distractions of world – a path doomed to failure – instead we
the body. The ‘‘true mother’’ of constancy is should follow the natural order of things. Rather
patience, defined as ‘‘a voluntary sufferance than attempt to reform God’s will, we should
without grudging of all things whatsoever can
attempt to reform ourselves.
happen to or in a man.’’44 Here we can see the
For Seneca, whatever happens is something
foundations laid for the modern popular image of
that must be endured rather than welcomed. This
the Stoic heroically enduring whatever fate
is emphasized in another text by his characteriza-
throws at him.45
tion of events as the product of cruel fortune:
This Lipsian image of Stoicism as heroic
‘‘They have ordered me to take a firm stand, like
endurance, patient fortitude, and voluntary
a sentry on guard, and to foresee all the attacks
sufferance is not without ancient precedent. By
and all the onslaughts of fortune (omnis conatus
training a classical philologist, Lipsius worked
closely on the texts of Seneca, eventually fortunae) long before they hit me.’’50
The acts of fortune are not something to be
producing an edition of Seneca in 1605. All of
the central arguments in De Constantia can be willed, but rather something to be suffered.
found in the works of Seneca; indeed, three of the Occasionally, Seneca develops this into an
four main arguments against public evils may be attitude of indifference, at one point suggesting
found in Letter 107 of Seneca’s correspondence that ‘‘the mark of true greatness is not to notice
with Lucilius. In this letter, we also find an that you have received a blow.’’51 However, he
attitude of endurance. The text’s central theme never develops it into an attitude of affirmation.
is unwanted external events. In response to Seneca endures and suffers what fate brings, and
Lucilius’s anguish in the face of some of his as such his attitude is one of resignation. The
slaves running away, Seneca reminds him that essence of the letter may be summed up by the
such troubles are neither unusual nor unex- maxim we find in it, optimum est pati – it is best
pected. He adds that they are also as inevitable to endure.52 As Lipsius himself summarizes the
and necessary as getting dirty when walking in thrust of this letter, one should suffer that which
the mud. For, Seneca reminds Lucilius, life is not one cannot amend (patere igitur, quod non
a delicate thing;46 rather, it is a journey in which emendas).53

163
deleuze’s stoicism

III human and cosmic stoicism hinder one’s desires and actions. These external
causes are other individual entities acting in
For Lipsius and Seneca, then, Stoicism involves accordance with their own natures. However, the
an ethic of heroic endurance that is quite Cosmos – Nature, God – includes everything that
different from Deleuze’s Nietzschean and exists and so has nothing external to it. As Cicero
Bousquetian reading of Stoicism as an ethic of writes in his summary of Stoic cosmology:
amor fati. At this point, it may be helpful to label ‘‘The various limited modes of being may
these two competing conceptions of Stoicism – I encounter many external obstacles to hinder
shall call them ‘‘human’’ and ‘‘cosmic’’ Stoicism, their perfect realization, but there can be nothing
respectively. that can frustrate Nature as a whole, since she
Human Stoicism is the popular conception of embraces and contains within herself all modes
Stoicism as heroic endurance or patient fortitude of being.’’57
that we have encountered in Lipsius and Only the Cosmos as a whole has complete
Seneca.54 The Human Stoic conceives the world freedom. It always acts according to its own
as something external and hostile. His Stoicism nature, never hindered by an external cause.
consists of a heroic response to whatever this From the perspective of the Cosmos, then, the
hostile world throws at him. Hegel’s presentation distinction between internal and external causes
of Stoicism in the Phenomenology of Spirit falls away. This distinction is thus always only
conforms to this image.55 For Hegel, the Stoic relative to the perspective of a particular finite
retreats into his consciousness because he has no mode of being. The philosophical task is to try –
control over the external world; the Stoic seeks so far as it is possible – to attain a cosmic
mental freedom because he has no physical perspective from which the boundary between
freedom. Rather than engaging in the reality of oneself and Nature is overcome. This forms a
master–slave conflicts, the Stoic withdraws into recurrent theme throughout the Meditations:
himself and preaches indifference towards what- ‘‘You came into the world as a part. You will
ever is outside of himself. What all of these vanish in that which gave you birth, or rather you
examples of Human Stoicism share is the will be taken up into its generative principle by
presumption of a rigid boundary between the the process of change.’’58
individual and the external world. In Marcus the task is a dissolution of the man–
In contrast to this there is Cosmic Stoicism. nature dichotomy which is presented in very
We can find this conception of Stoicism in the physical and material terms, reflecting the
works of Epictetus and Marcus Aurelius. influence of Heraclitus. In Epictetus, the same
Although both Epictetus and Marcus focus in task is presented as a desire to become one with
upon the self – in Epictetus the concern is with God, to will all of God’s actions as if they were
what is ‘‘up to us’’ (eph’ hêmin); in Marcus one’s own. A true Stoic, says Epictetus, is ‘‘a man
the self is an ‘‘inner citadel’’ (akropolis) – the who desires to be of one mind with God, and
principal motivation behind this concern with the never to cast blame on God or man again.’’59 Of
self is a desire to overcome the boundary between course, unity with Nature and unity with God
the individual self and the Cosmos so that there is amount to the same thing for a Stoic. The
no longer any opposition between the two. For important point here is that for Cosmic Stoicism,
the Stoics – like Spinoza after them – the only the boundary between the individual and Nature
truly free being is God, identified with Nature, is overcome, and there is no longer an opposition
for only God encounters no opposition. between the will of the individual and the will
According to Stoic physics, any individual of God, which is identified with fate.60 For
entity will act according to its own nature or Epictetus, ‘‘my wish is always for what actually
internal cause – conceived as a desire for self- comes to pass.’’61 In his Handbook, he enjoins us:
preservation – unless hindered by some external ‘‘Do not seek events to happen as you want, but
cause.56 From the perspective of the individual, want events as they happen, and your life will
there are a whole series of external causes that flow well.’’62

164
sellars

This idea is elaborated in Discourses 1.12. In remedy for ressentiment. It is a fatalism without
this text, Epictetus defines freedom as having all revolt against what happens, a welcoming of what
things happen in accordance with one’s choice or comes to pass by chance, free from any desire to
will (prohairesis).63 However, this should not be change or rebel against one’s situation –
conceived as the freedom to act randomly or ‘‘accepting oneself as if fated, not wishing oneself
without reason; instead, it must involve ‘‘learning ‘different.’ ’’68 Thus, it involves an identification
to will that things should happen as they do.’’64 of one’s own will with fate, the will of the
In a striking passage, Epictetus offers some Cosmos. This Russian fatalism correlates with
examples and outlines the status of his ethical Cosmic Stoicism, while Turkish fatalism corre-
position: lates with Human Stoicism.
How might we try to explain the existence of
You are wretched and discontented, and if you these two quite different Stoic positions? We can
are alone, you call it desolation, but if you are
do so by conceiving them as two distinct stages
with men, you call them cheats and robbers
on the path of philosophical progression towards
[. . .] whereas you ought, when you live alone,
to call that peace and freedom, and compare the ideal of the sage. For a Human Stoic such as
yourself to the gods; and when you are in Seneca, much of Stoic thinking about fate has
company, not to call it a crowd and a tumult been taken on board, but fate – the will of the
and a vexation, but a feast and a festival, and Cosmic God – is still conceived as something
thus accept all things with contentment. external to oneself. For a Cosmic Stoic like
What, then, is the punishment of those who Epictetus, by contrast, the individual is conceived
do not? To be just as they are. Is a person as part of fate; one’s own will is identified with
discontented at being alone? Let him be in the will of God. Epictetus expands his conception
desolation. [. . .] ‘‘Throw him into prison.’’ of his will to include all causes, both internal and
What kind of prison? Where he already is, for
external to himself. To borrow Deleuze’s Zen-
he is there against his will, and wherever any
Stoic analogy, the Human Stoic is the disciple
one is against his will, that is to him a prison;
just as Socrates was not in prison, for he was who has not yet mastered the koan; the Cosmic
willingly there.65 Stoic is the master who has attained enlight-
enment.69 That is to say, the Human Stoic
To translate this into Nietzschean terms, the remains at the level of a philosophical apprentice
ethical imperative behind amor fati is simply who has understood Stoic doctrines but has not
the opportunity to avoid having to live a life of yet digested those doctrines to the point where
ressentiment. they will transform his entire life. The Cosmic
This desire to overcome the division between Stoic, by contrast, has fully digested those
the individual and Nature (¼ Cosmos, God, fate) doctrines to the point where they have trans-
is quite distinct from the attitude we encountered formed his habitual beliefs and dispositions.70
in Seneca and Lipsius, in which the existence of While the Stoic beginner continues to grit his
such a division is a necessary precondition for the teeth in the face of harsh fortune, the Stoic
endurance of external assaults upon the indivi- master suffers nothing, for he knows that nothing
dual. These two distinct attitudes correlate with bad can happen to him, no matter what fate may
what Nietzsche calls ‘‘Turkish’’ and ‘‘Russian’’ bring.71
fatalism.66 For Nietzsche, Turkish fatalism
opposes man, and fate against each other as two
distinct entities; one can try to resist fate, but
IV deleuze’s stoic ethics
eventually fate will always win. This leads one Deleuze’s presentation of Stoic ethics as the
into a state of resignation in the face of fate when precursor to Nietzsche’s amor fati is thus
in fact, Nietzsche comments, man ‘‘is himself legitimate, notwithstanding its distance from the
a piece of fate.’’67 This latter idea is developed popular conception of Stoicism as heroic endur-
in his comments on Russian fatalism. In Ecce ance. It is worth noting, however, that so far we
Homo, Nietzsche presents Russian fatalism as the have encountered two distinct senses in which,

165
deleuze’s stoicism

in a Deleuzian–Stoic ethic, an event may be (LS 174/149). It is important to be clear here


incorporated into oneself. about the way in which Deleuze understands the
The first sense involves conceiving oneself no word ‘‘ethics.’’74 Following Foucault, Deleuze
longer as a static physical entity but rather as a draws a distinction between ‘‘ethics’’ and ‘‘mor-
process or series of events. An individual ality.’’75 By ‘‘morality,’’ they both understand a
conceived as a process will be constituted by a series of restrictive rules and regulations that
series of events, and each new event – no matter judge a person’s actions with reference to some
what its content – will become a necessary part of transcendent or objective norm. By ‘‘ethics,’’ in
who one is. This is the lesson that Deleuze draws contrast, they understand a series of optional or
from Bousquet. It also reflects Deleuze’s wider immanent modes of behaviour that form a mode
commitment to a process ontology, for which he of existing or way of life.76 According to
draws upon Bergson, Whitehead, and others. Foucault, Greek and Graeco-Roman philosophy
The second sense in which an event may be were far more concerned with ethics than
incorporated into oneself involves dissolving the morality, the notable exception being Plato,77
boundary between oneself and the rest of Nature, while Deleuze uses this distinction to analyse
identifying one’s own will with the will of the Spinoza. Rejecting morality, for Deleuze the
Cosmos, which is, in turn, identified with fate. ethical choice is one between different modes of
This is the project that we encountered in existence. There are a number of ways in which
Epictetus and Marcus Aurelius. In this second alternative modes of existence may be assessed
sense, the task at hand is to see oneself no longer and then selected. The important point is that
as an isolated individual but rather as but one there is no transcendent set of values against
part of a unified Nature. This is a lesson that which they may be judged as either right or
Deleuze draws from Spinoza. wrong. Instead, they can only be assessed by
Indeed, these two senses are the two poles of immanent criteria, such as their power of
Stoic ethics proposed by Goldschmidt: the logical creation,78 their cultivation of joy, or – to put it
pole and the physical pole.72 The logical pole, in the language of ancient ethics – the extent to
exemplified by Bousquet, receives most of which they embody eudaimonia (well-being).
Deleuze’s attention in his explicit discussion of Deleuze’s rejection of ressentiment and affirma-
Stoic ethics in The Logic of Sense, but the tion of amor fati is on the basis of the mode of
physical pole is also touched upon. In some brief existence that the former expresses: ‘‘there are
remarks that prefigure his later work with things one can only do or say through mean-
Guattari, Deleuze considers what may be learned spiritedness, a life based on hatred, or bitterness
from the experiences of the alcoholic or the toward life’’ (P 138/100).79 Elsewhere, he writes:
schizophrenic for whom the rigid boundaries of
the self have begun to crack. How might we, we always have the beliefs, feelings and
Deleuze asks, replicate those experiences without thoughts that we deserve given our way of
being or our style of life. There are things that
falling into the black holes of alcoholism or
can only be said, felt or conceived, values
madness? His provisional reply is to comment
which can only be adhered to, on condition of
‘‘How much we have yet to learn from Stoicism ‘‘base’’ evaluation, ‘‘base’’ living and thinking.
. . .’’ (LS 184/158). Later, Deleuze and Guattari (NP 2/1–2)
will develop this thought into a project aimed at
dissolving the division between individual and Or, as Epictetus put it earlier, the punishment for
Nature, in a manner close to the physical pole of those who choose not to affirm the event is
Stoic ethics.73 simply ‘‘to be just as they are,’’ to continue to live
For Deleuze, this project of affirming the event a life of bitterness and resentment.80 The ethical
also forms the basis for an ethics. As we have choice, for Deleuze, is one between a life of
seen, he writes ‘‘Either ethics makes no sense at bitterness and a life of joy.
all, or this is what it means and has nothing else We can see, then, an affinity between Deleuze,
to say: not to be unworthy of what happens to us’’ Nietzsche, and Cosmic Stoics such as Epictetus

166
sellars

and Marcus Aurelius on the question of affirming this implies the affirmation not only of our entire
fate. It is important, however, not to emphasize life but also of the entire world, for every other
this affinity to the extent that the remaining part of the cosmos and every
differences are ignored. Although the Stoics do past event are implicated in
hold a cosmological doctrine of cyclical recur- the coming to be of that single
rence, there is no connection between this and event.84 This is not constantia;
their affirmation of fate in the way that there is it is amor fati.85
for Nietzsche, for instance.81 For the Stoics, it is
the providential ordering of Nature that under-
pins their affirmation of fate. It goes without abbreviations to works
saying that neither Nietzsche nor Deleuze would by deleuze
identify fate with providence in the way that the
Stoics do. For Deleuze, the affirmation of the AO L’anti-Oedipe, with F. Guattari (Paris:
event is the affirmation of the aleatory event, Minuit, 1972); Anti-Oedipus, trans.
such as Bousquet’s wound. His ethic of the event R. Hurley, M. Seem and H.R. Lane
conceives the event as a dice throw rather than a (New York: Viking, 1977)
necessary component of a providentially ordered CC Critique et clinique (Paris: Minuit, 1993);
system. Here, he is explicitly following Nietzsche, Essays Critical and Clinical, trans. D.W.
for whom the dice throw signifies the affirmation Smith and M.A. Greco (Minneapolis: U of
of chance.82 In order to play well, to affirm the Minnesota P, 1997)
outcome of the dice throw, it is necessary to deny D Dialogues, with C. Parnet (Paris:
the existence of any purpose or end in Nature. Flammarion, 1977); Dialogues, trans.
This is a significant difference between Deleuze H. Tomlinson and B. Habberjam (London:
and Nietzsche, on the one hand, and the Stoics, Athlone, 1987)
on the other. DR Différence et répétition (Paris: PUF, 1968);
Difference and Repetition, trans. P. Patton
(London: Athlone, 1994)
V affirmation versus steadfastness LS Logique du sens (Paris: Minuit, 1969); The
Let us conclude by returning to our opening Logic of Sense, trans. M. Lester (New York:
quotation from Bernold. According to Bernold, Columbia UP, 1990)
‘‘even though he [Deleuze] had explicated MP Mille plateaux, with F. Guattari (Paris:
Chrysippus, it is above all his steadfastness Minuit, 1980); A Thousand Plateaus,
(constance) that earned him the name of Stoic.’’ trans. B. Massumi (London: Athlone, 1988)
While agreeing with Bernold that Deleuze’s NP Nietzsche et la philosophie (Paris: PUF,
Stoicism goes well beyond his brief explicit 1962); Nietzsche and Philosophy, trans.
comments on the Stoics, it should by now be H. Tomlinson (London: Athlone, 1983)
clear that it would be a mistake to characterize P Pourparlers, 1972–1990 (Paris: Minuit,
Deleuze’s Stoic ethic as constance, which we 1990); Negotiations: 1972–1990, trans.
might translate as ‘‘steadfastness’’ or ‘‘con- M. Joughin (New York: Columbia UP,
stancy.’’ This notion of constance is the direct 1995)
descendent of Lipsius’s constantia which, as we PLB Le pli, Leibniz et le baroque (Paris:
have seen, is quite different from the ethic Minuit, 1988); The Fold: Leibniz and
proposed by Deleuze. Deleuze’s Stoicism is the Baroque, trans. T. Conley (London:
neither the Stoicism of Lipsius nor that of Athlone, 1993)
Hegel; it is rather a Nietzschean and SPE Spinoza et le problème de l’expression
Bousquetian Stoicism.83 In this latter form of (Paris: Minuit, 1968); Expressionism in
Stoicism, the affirmation of a single event implies Philosophy: Spinoza, trans. M. Joughin
the affirmation of all of existence. If, argues (New York: Zone, 1992)
Nietzsche, we can say yes to a single event, then

167
deleuze’s stoicism

SPP Spinoza, Philosophie pratique (Paris: philosophies pluralistes d’Angleterre et d’Ame¤rique


Minuit, 1981); Spinoza: Practical (Paris: Alcan, 1920) and Vers le concret, E¤tudes d’his-
Philosophy, trans. R. Hurley (San toire de la philosophie contemporaine (Paris: Vrin,
Francisco: City Lights, 1988) 1932).
11 See LS16/7 and DR 82/59.
notes 12 See CC171/137.
1 Andre¤ Bernold, ‘‘Suidas,’’ Philosophie 47 (1995): 13 See LS152^58/127^33.
8 ^9, at 8 (trans. Timothy S. Murphy; see 5http://
14 See esp. SPP.
www.webdeleuze.com4).
15 This piece was first published as ‘‘Les
2 Gilles Deleuze, Logique du sens (Paris: Minuit,
1969); The Logic of Sense, trans. M. Lester intellectuels et le pouvoir,’’ L’Arc 49 (1972): 3^10.
(New York: Columbia UP, 1990), abbreviated to It is reprinted in a variety of places, including ID
LS, followed by French and then English pagina- 288 ^98/206 ^13. I shall supply page references to
tion. See the separate list of abbreviations for ID, but I may quote from the translation in
works by Deleuze, used according to the same Foucault Live: Collected Interviews, 1961^1984, trans.
convention. Note also that references to L. Hochroth and J. Johnston (New York:
Nietzsche are cross-referenced to KSA ¼ Semiotext(e),1996).
Sa«mtliche Werke: Kritische Studienausgabe, eds. 16 ‘‘Les intellectuels et le pouvoir,’’ L’Arc 49 (1972):
G. Colli and M. Montinari, 15 vols (Berlin: de 3^10 (¼ ID 288/206).
Gruyter,1980; 2nd edn 1988).
17 Ibid. (ID 290/208).
3 See LS 13^21/4 ^11. Here, Deleuze draws upon
E¤mile Bre¤hier’s La the¤orie des incorporels dans 18 On this theme in Stoicism, see John
l’ancien sto|« cisme (Paris: Vrin, 1928; 9th edn 1997). Sellars, The Art of Living: The Stoics on the Nature
For a brief overview of Stoic ontology, see John and Function of Philosophy (Aldershot: Ashgate,
Sellars, Stoicism (Chesham: Acumen, 2006) 81^ 86. 2003).

4 On this, see n. 35 below. 19 See MP185^204/149^ 66 with discussion in John


Sellars, ‘‘The Point of View of the Cosmos:
5 For Deleuze’s account of the Stoic ‘‘image of the Deleuze, Romanticism, Stoicism,’’ Pli: The Warwick
philosopher,’’ see LS152^58/127^33. Journal of Philosophy 8 (1999): 1^24.
6 There are few references to the Stoics before 20 Deleuze introduces the concept of a
the 1968 ^1969 trilogy of LS, DR, and SPE. Passing distribution according to nomos in DR 53^54/36
references appear in a number of later works, and develops it into nomadology in MP 434 ^527/
including MP and PLB. The most sustained discus- 351^ 423. For Zeno, see the essay in Plutarch’s
sion after LS is in D 77^ 81/62^ 66, although the Moralia entitled On the Fortune or Virtue of
form of the work deliberately makes it unclear Alexander 329a ^ b.
whether this should be attributed to Deleuze or
to his collaborator, Claire Parnet. 21 See Victor Goldschmidt, Le syste'me sto|« cien et
l’ide¤e de temps (Paris: Vrin,1953; 4th edn 1979).
7 See p. vii of the English edition of Dialogues;
for the French version of this Preface, see DRF 22 Goldschmidt 77^99.
284 ^ 87.
23 On this, see Sellars,‘‘The Point of View of the
8 See ibid. and note also P 199/145. Deleuze’s most Cosmos’’ 12^22.
substantial comments on Whitehead can be found
24 Goldschmidt 99^124.
in PLB, esp. 103^12/76 ^ 82, but note also DR 364/
284 ^ 85. 25 Goldschmidt 99.
9 William James, Essays in Radical Empiricism 26 Epictetus, Discourses 2.10.5; cited in
(London: Longmans, Green & Co.,1912) 41. Goldschmidt 90.
10 On this topic, Deleuze was influenced by the 27 Marcus Aurelius, Meditations 5.8; cited in
work of his teacher Jean Wahl; see esp. Les Goldschmidt 101.

168
sellars
28 This line is also quoted in D 80/65,Qu’est-ce que 35 It would require a separate paper to expli-
la philosophie? (Paris: Minuit, 1991) 151, and cate the supposedly Stoic concepts of aio“n and
‘‘L’immanence: une vie . . .,’’ Philosophie 47 (1995): chronos, but some preliminary remarks may be
3^7, at 7. In LS, the source of this quotation is not made. The theory of time (chronos) attributed
stated, although in Qu’est-ce que la philosophie? it is to the Stoic Chrysippus in the ancient sources
given as Bousquet’s Les Capitales (Paris: Le Cercle does indeed suggest two notions of the present,
du Livre, 1955) 103. I have not been able to find it one with a certain extension, the other an
there or anywhere in Les Capitales; it can however extensionless limit between past and future
be found in Rene¤ Nelli, ‘‘Joe Bousquet et son (see, e.g., the texts by Stobaeus and Plutarch
double,’’ Cahiers du Sud 303 (1950): 177^ 86, at 180, translated in A.A. Long and D.N. Sedley, The
which Deleuze cites in LS174/348. For a discussion Hellenistic Philosophers 1 (Cambridge: Cambridge
of Bousquet see Ferdinand Alquie¤,The Philosophy of UP, 1987) 304 ^ 05). Most commentators have
Surrealism, trans. Bernard Waldrop (Ann Arbor: either attempted to reconcile these or dis-
U of Michigan P,1965) esp.165^72. As Alquie¤ com- missed Chrysippus’s position as incoherent. It is
ments, Bousquet affirmed the event of his wound Goldschmidt who attributes a dual conception
as the origin of his subsequent career as a writer. It of the present moment to Chrysippus. He then
is worth noting that Alquie¤, one of Deleuze’s tea- proposes that one of these conceptions is
chers, also labelled Bousquet a Stoic (‘‘I do not call echoed by Marcus Aurelius, who uses the word
him stoic, wanting what he is, but one, being what eternity (aio“n) a number of times. Deleuze’s
he is’’; ibid.167). For a brief discussion of Bousquet ‘‘Stoic’’ theory of aio“n and chronos is thus the
and Stoicism, see Nicole Bhattacharya, Joe« product of Goldschmidt’s highly speculative and
Bousquet: Une expe¤rience spirituelle (Geneva: Droz, synthetic reconstruction that draws upon frag-
1998) 452^55. mentary and inconclusive reports of Chrysippus
and the Meditations of Marcus. In neither
29 Alquie¤, The Philosophy of Surrealism 168.
Chrysippus nor Marcus is aio“n used as a techni-
30 Ibid. 169. This part of Alquie¤’s text reprints cal term to refer to a specific conception of
his 1950 article on Bousquet, ‘‘Joe Bousquet et time. Goldschmidt’s reading of Marcus has been
la morale du langage,’’ Cahiers du Sud 303 (1950): criticized in Pierre Hadot, The Inner Citadel: The
187^90, cited by Deleuze in LS174/348. Meditations of Marcus Aurelius, trans. Michael
Chase (Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1998) 137.
31 See LS175/149 and note also D 80/65. Nietzsche
first introduced the concept of amor fati inThe Gay 36 The Oxford English Dictionary, 2nd edn (Oxford:
Science 276 (KSA 3,521) but perhaps its clearest Clarendon Press,1989) vol.16, 746.
expression can be found in Ecce Homo ‘‘Why I Am
37 Justus Lipsius, De Constantia Libri Duo, Qui allo-
So Clever’’ 10 (KSA 6,297): ‘‘My formula for great-
quium praecipue continent in Publicis malis (Leiden:
ness in a human being is amor fati: that one wants
Plantin, 1584); trans. John Stradling, in Justus
nothing to be other than it is, not in the future,
Lipsius, On Constancy, ed. J. Sellars (Exeter: Bristol
not in the past, not in all eternity. Not merely to
Phoenix Press, 2006).
endure that which happens of Necessity, still less
to dissemble it ^ all idealism is untruthfulness in 38 For the publishing history, see A.M. Van De
the face of necessity ^ but to love it’’ (trans. in Bilt, Lipsius’ De Constantia en Seneca (Nijmegen:
Keith Ansell Pearson and Duncan Large (eds.), The Dekker & Van De Vegt, 1946) 105^ 08, and the
Nietzsche Reader (Oxford: Blackwell, 2006) 509). comprehensive bibliography in F. Van Der
Note also the Epilogue to Nietzsche contra Wagner Haeghen, Bibliographie Lipsienne: Oeuvres de Juste
(KSA 6,436). Deleuze, of course, has much more Lipse, 2 vols (Gand: Universite¤ de Gand, 1886)
to say about Nietzschean affirmation in NP, esp. vol.1, 71^177.
201^17/175^ 89.
39 See Diderot’s entry on ‘‘Sto|« cisme’’ in the
32 Joe« Bousquet, Traduit du silence (Paris: Encyclope¤die, ou Dictionnaire Raisonne¤ des Sciences,
Gallimard, 1941; 2nd edn 1967) 11; cited in Alquie¤, des Arts et des Me¤tiers (Neufchastel, 1751^ 65)
The Philosophy of Surrealism 170. vol.15, 525^33, esp. 532^33.
33 See LS175/149. 40 Seneca, Letters 28.2; see also104.7.
34 See LS176/150. 41 Epictetus, Handbook 1.1^3.

169
deleuze’s stoicism
42 Lipsius, De Constantia 1.4. 60 For the Stoics, the will of God, identified with
fate, is simply the order of material causes in the
43 As we shall see later, there are also some
Cosmos. Thus, as Cicero comments in On
important differences between Lipsius and
Divination 1.126, Stoic fate is not the fate of
Epictetus.
superstition but rather the fate of physics.
44 Lipsius, De Constantia 1.4.
61 Epictetus, Discourses 4.7.20. On this theme, see
45 The remainder of the dialogue offers four Andre¤-JeanVoelke, L’ide¤e de volonte¤ dans le sto|« cisme
arguments designed to aid the internal transfor- (Paris: PUF,1973) 96 ^105.
mation necessary to overcome public evils. For
62 Epictetus, Handbook 8.
further discussion, see John Sellars, ‘‘Justus
Lipsius’s De Constantia, A Stoic Spiritual Exercise,’’ 63 Epictetus, Discourses 1.12.9.
PoeticsToday (forthcoming).
64 Ibid.1.12.15; see also1.12.17.
46 Seneca, Letters 107.2.
65 Ibid.1.12.20 ^23.
47 Ibid.107.3.
66 On these terms in Nietzsche, see Joan
48 Ibid.107.7. Stambaugh, ‘‘Amor dei and Amor fati: Spinoza and
Nietzsche,’’ in J.C. O’Flaherty, T.F. Sellner and R.M.
49 Ibid.107.9. Helm (eds.), Studies in Nietzsche and the Judaeo-
50 Seneca,Consolation to Helvia his Mother 5.3. Christian Tradition (Chapel Hill: U of North
Carolina P,1985) 130 ^ 42, esp.133^34.
51 Seneca, On Anger 3.25.3: Proprium est magnitudi-
nis uerae non sentire percussum. 67 On Turkish fatalism (Tu«rkenfatalismus ^ trans-
lated as ‘‘Mohammedan fatalism’’ by Hollingdale),
52 Seneca, Letters 107.9. see Human, All Too Human II: The Wanderer and his
53 Justus Lipsius, Senecae Opera (Antwerp: Shadow 61 (KSA 2,580), translated in Human, All
Plantin-Moretus,1605) 631. Too Human, trans. R.J. Hollingdale (Cambridge:
Cambridge UP,1986) 325. Leibniz also commented
54 ‘‘Human Stoicism’’ is a shortening of on Turkish fatalism (which he labeled Fatum
‘‘Human, all too Human, Stoicism’’ which (with Mahometanum) in x 55 of the Theodicy, attributing
apologies to Nietzsche) captures the anthro- it to the effects of hashish. See G.W. Leibniz,
pocentric character of this conception of Theodicy, trans. E.M. Huggard (La Salle: Open
Stoicism. Court,1985) 153.
55 See G.W.F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, 68 See Ecce Homo ‘‘Why I Am So Wise’’ 6 (KSA
trans. A.V. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977) 6,272^73), translated in Basic Writings of Nietzsche,
esp. 119^26. Note also his assessment in his trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Modern
Lectures on the Philosophy of History, trans. J. Sibree Library, 1968) 685^ 87. Later in the same text, of
(London: George Bell, 1890) 329: ‘‘for the systems course, Nietzsche will return to the theme of
of that time ^ Stoicism, Epicureanism, and amor fati (at KSA 6,297), on which see n. 31 above.
Scepticism ^ although within their common
sphere opposed to each other, had the same 69 For Deleuze’s Stoic-Zen analogy, see LS 18/8,
general purport, viz., rendering the soul 161^ 62/136^37,171^72/146.
absolutely indifferent to everything which the 70 On the topics of philosophical apprentices,
real world had to offer.’’ training, and digestion, see Sellars, The Art of
Living, passim.
56 On the Stoics and self-preservation, see
Sellars, Stoicism 107^ 09. 71 So Richard Sorabji, Emotion and Peace of Mind
(Oxford: Oxford UP, 2000) 1: ‘‘[Stoicism] is not
57 Cicero, On the Nature ofthe Gods 2.35.
a matter of gritting your teeth. It is about seeing
58 Marcus Aurelius, Meditations 4.14; note also things differently, so that you do not need to grit
4.21, 6.24. For discussion, see Sellars, The Art of your teeth.’’
Living 150 ^54.
72 See Goldschmidt, Le syste'me sto|« cien 79 and
59 Epictetus, Discourses 2.19.26. LS 169/144. These two senses also echo Deleuze’s

170
sellars
distinction between subject-type individuation and 34: ‘‘Joy emerges as the sole motive for
event-type individuation, on which see P156/115. philosophizing.’’
73 This project runs through both volumes of 79 See also SPE 248/269: ‘‘there are things one
Capitalism and Schizophrenia. It is announced in the cannot do or even say, believe, feel, think, unless
opening pages of AO, 7^ 8/1^2 and 10 ^11/4 ^5. It is one is weak, enslaved, impotent; and other things
developed at greater length (and with an allusion one cannot do, feel, and so on, unless one is free
to Stoicism) in MP185^204/149^ 66.For a prelimin- or strong.’’
ary discussion, see Sellars, ‘‘The Point of View of
80 See Epictetus, Discourses 1.12.20 ^23, quoted
the Cosmos.’’
above.
74 For a helpful account of Deleuze’s approach
81 On this point, see Hadot, The Inner Citadel
to ethics, see Daniel W. Smith, ‘‘The Place of
144 ^ 45.
Ethics in Deleuze’s Philosophy: Three Questions
of Immanence,’’ in Eleanor Kaufman and Kevin Jon 82 See NP 29^31/25^27.
Heller (eds.), Deleuze and Guattari (Minneapolis:
83 I am not convinced by Alain Badiou’s claim that
U of Minnesota P,1998) 251^ 69.
Deleuze’s Stoicism (which he acknowledges as sig-
75 See the interview between Deleuze and Didier nificant) is ultimately a philosophy of death (see his
Eribon from 1986, reprinted in P 129^38/94 ^101, Deleuze (Paris: Hachette, 1997) 23^24). I suspect
esp.137^ 8/100, commenting on Foucault’s articula- that this reflects a conception of Stoicism that
tion of this distinction inThe Use of Pleasure, trans. relies upon Hegel’s presentation (see n. 55 above).
Robert Hurley (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1992)
84 See Nietzsche’s notebooks, 7[38] 1886 ^ 87
25^32. However, Deleuze had already made this
(KSA 12,307^ 08), translated in Friedrich
distinction in his 1970 book Spinoza (Paris: PUF,
Nietzsche,Writings from the Late Notebooks, trans.
1970) esp. 29: ‘‘Ethics, which is to say, a typology Kate Sturge (Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2003)
of immanent modes of existence, replaces 135^36.
Morality, which always refers existence to trans-
cendent values’’ (repr. in SPP 35/23).This was pub- 85 I would like to thank Dan Smith for reading an
lished just one year after LS. earlier draft of this paper.

76 Thus, the distinction here is subtly different


from the distinction between ethics (Sittlichkeit)
and morality (Moralita«t) articulated by Hegel.
77 SeeThe Use of Pleasure 30. In the interview ‘‘On
the Genealogy of Ethics,’’ Foucault explicitly
relates this to Stoicism; seeThe Foucault Reader, ed.
Paul Rabinow (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1991)
341.
78 If there is a summum bonum in Deleuze’s philo-
sophy, then it might be‘‘creativity’’ (or alternatively
‘‘life,’’ defined as a creative process); see, e.g., CC
168 ^ 69/134 ^35 and now P. Hallward, Out of this
World: Deleuze and the Philosophy of Creation
(London: Verso, 2006). In his work on Spinoza,
Deleuze characterizes this as a power of acting,
which he associates with joyful passions.
See SPE 252/273^74. Note also that joy (chara) is
one of the Stoic ‘‘good passions’’ (eupatheiai), on John Sellars
which see Sellars, Stoicism 118 ^19. For Deleuze, Wolfson College
‘‘joy,’’ another potential candidate for his summum Oxford
bonum, is closely associated with one’s power OX2 6UD
of acting; see SPP 139/101; note also P 14/6 UK
and Deleuze, Nietzsche (Paris: PUF, 1965) E-mail: john.sellars@wolfson.ox.ac.uk

Вам также может понравиться