Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 25

HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 333

Justice hope was not taken into consideration. How-


ever, this is also the case, with concessions,
A: a ad>a la. – G: Gerechtigkeit. – F: justice. –
for Ernst Bloch, who, in other respects, knew
R: spravedlivost’. – S: justicia. –
very well how to inherit the biblical writings.
C: zhengyi, gongping
He saw perspectives for a concept of justice
I. Biblical tradition – The demand for justice from below only in the natural law of the
is for social movements just as self-evident sects with their ’social-revolutionary desire
as it is theoretically contested. In everyday for an originary state’ (GA 6, 42), but not in
struggles about survival and the quality of the Old Testament, whose concept of justice
life, it is experiences of injustice that prompt he understood, under the influence of
humans to engage in resistance. Here, the Marcion, only as despotic and patriarchal
immediate hopes for reparation, for the (52). Yet even he came close to a biblical
eradication of injustice and the restoration understanding of justice when he saw the
of law can form the point of departure for beginnings of a ‘real justice’ in the ‘images
the development of a fuller desire for justice of retaliation of the Last Judgement’ which,
as the quintessence of a new society free as a form of justice ‘from below’, turned
from oppression, exploitation and exclusion. against the ‘intrinsic injustice’ of justice
Moralists and demagogues, however, also practiced as revenging and dispensing (228
set out from this ‘hunger and thirst for et sqq.).
justice’ (Mt 5,6), removing justice from
struggles and transforming it into an abstract, 1. In the Hebrew Bible, justice is one of the
‘eternal’ value whose realisation is to be foundational themes or even ‘the central
awaited from on high. The polemics of Marx theme par excellence’, ‘the centre’ (Dietrich
and Engels were aimed above all against 1989). ‘The fact that the relationship with
such ossification in ideological forms (e.g., the divine crosses the relationship with men
MECW 6, 143, 193; 23, 377; 25, 18; 35, 94; 37, and coincides with social justice is therefore
337). The question is how such a necessary what epitomizes the entire spirit of the
critique of ideology can communicate with Jewish Bible’ (Levinas 1998 [1963] 19). The
attempts that seek to make fruitful the diversity of relationships of the vocabulary
utopian-critical potential of ideas concerning of ‘justice’ and its conceptual milieu refuses
justice rooted in the experiences of everyday precise definitions. The changing formations
life. of social life have left behind numerous
Even though social movements, not only traces in the biblical understanding of justice,
in Europe but in all ‘Christianised’ parts of with different views, demands, experiences
the world, have time and again appealed to of injustice, images of law and ideals of
biblical ideas of justice, it is precisely these justice. This extends from a tribal ethos to
ideas which have hardly been analysed in ideas of cosmic justice from ancient oriental
Marxism. Marx, despite his critique of kingdoms. The tension between positive law
Mammon and Moloch recalling those of the and critical ideas and tendencies of justice
prophets, saw no positive starting-point in has worked in the favour of the poor and
the biblical tradition with regard to the con- their legal positions – even if not always.
cept of justice. This may also be connected In the ancient oriental environment
to his tendency, in the heat of the argument surrounding Israel, law and justice were
with religious communists such as Weitling worshipped as goddesses or gods who gave
and Hess, to regard references to the religious kings the capacity to govern justly. The name
legacy as an obstacle to an analysis of society of Melchizedek (pre-Israelite king of
without illusions. The possibility of a reflex- Jerusalem) highlights this: ‘my king is Zedek’
ive relationship to a common tradition of (justice as divinity). In Egypt, Maat, the

Historical Materialism, volume 13:3 (333–357)


© Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, 2005
Also available online – www.brill.nl
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 334

334 • Bastiaan Wielenga, Hermann Klenner and Susanne Lettow

divine daughter of the sun god Re, stood relations in which problems of Law were
for truth and justice as the very quintessence posed concretely. Legal entitlements,
of an adequate cosmic and social order as particularly of the poor, and legal decisions
well as a personal praxis. Instructions for were accordingly judged with a view to the
the implementation of justice by the divine restoration of community.
Pharaoh, however, are not found in the legal In the monarchical period – from David
codices as in Mesopotamia. There, Shamash, to the Exile – this usage of the word was
the sun god, was worshipped as the god connected to elements of the ancient oriental
of justice as well (Epsztein 1986, 4, 18 et ideology of kingship and, when necessary,
sqq.; von Rad 1958, 374). The tradition was used for the legitimation of new forms
of codification of social laws was effective of domination. Justice was regarded in the
all over Mesopotamia. The Codex of King ancient Orient as the foundation of the kingly
Hammurabi claimed, in the name of throne (Koch 1976, 509 et sq.). A similar
Shamash, to establish justice and to destroy perspective can be found in some of the
wrong-doers so that the strong did not Psalms and the Proverbs of Israel (e.g. Ps 89,
oppress the weak. The laws were supposed 15; Pr 16, 12). By virtue of the divine gift of
to protect the rights of orphans and widows. justice, the king was supposed to ensure the
The same Codex, however, divided society stability of the law, to protect the poor from
into three classes. There were echoes of the exploitation and the weak from violence
Babylonian tradition in the collections of the and thus guarantee a just order (e.g. Ps 72, 1
laws of Israel, but, just as much, important et sqq.; cf. W. Schottroff 1999, 5 et sqq.).
differences that were founded in God’s Therefore, the cosmic order, which was
covenant with the people as a whole. Thus, supposed to bestow life and social well-
justice was not worshipped as a separate being, was guaranteed by the king. Marx’s
divinity, but was regarded as an attribute of critique of ideology had, in such a courtly
the single God in Heaven who allowed it to theology, a fertile field – which, of course,
become operative upon the earth (e.g. Ps 85, the prophets of Israel had long ago ploughed,
11 et sqq.). YHWH (Yaweh), therefore, as the preventing the deification of the kings of
subject of justice, defined not only that which Israel from finding general acceptance. A
was divine, but also that which was truly theo-cosmic understanding of justice here
just (Ps 82). functions without the mediation of earthly
The Hebrew vocabulary for justice, law rulers (e.g. Ps 85) as it was directly and
and rectitude was related primarily to social messianically promised to the people.
justice, just as in the societies surrounding This is evidence for the fact that ancient
it. An overriding legal interpretation that oriental ideology of justice must not be
predominated for a long time, mediated by assumed to be always on the side of power.
the Latin translation of ‘iustitia’, is hardly If the protection of the poor and liberation
held anymore in Old Testament scholarship. from subjugation were formulated as duties
‘The concept of a punishing tsedaqah is not of the king (Ps 72), criteria for the wielding
supported; it would be a contradictio in of power were provided which could also
adiecto’ (von Rad 1958, 375). Other words be applied critically. This possibility arose
were used to talk about judgement, pun- under the conditions of a mode of production
ishment and reward. Justice – as a trans- founded upon a system of tribute, due to
lation of ‘tsedaqah’ – regarded a whole scale the fact that the community structures from
of relationships in which humans have to before the institution of the state continued
prove themselves to be ‘just people’ in to function on the local level – even if under
relation to each other, to the world and to pressure from the obligation to render tribute
the environment and, in all of these, to – and gave the material basis for an ethos
God. As a relational concept for righteous of solidarity not based upon domination.
[gemeinschaftstreu] behaviour, ‘tsedaqah’ The ethos of the association of tribes from
included both personal conduct toward before the state not only continued to be
others and also the fundamental social effective in the time of the kings, but also
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 335

HKWM – Justice • 335

survived the fall of the monarchy, so that of the rich, whose houses were full of stolen
the Torah republic after the Exile was able goods and who lay waiting to ambush the
to hark back to it. poor (Ps 10), alongside a critique of the eco-
An exegesis of the Bible that interprets nomically stronger who displaced the weaker
discussions in the Old Testament of justice (Ezekiel 34, 17 et sqq.).
and law only in the context of a way of Accordingly, not only the kings were
thinking which confirms the established urged to practice justice and righteousness,
order fails to take into account this dimension but all people: ‘seek justice, help the
of resistance. In contrast, the specificity of oppressed’ (Isaiah 1, 17 et sq.), do justice to
the case is demonstrated in the critique of one in a conflict against another, practise no
injustice of the prophets. On the one hand, violence against strangers, orphans and
they referred back to the tradition of Exodus widows ( Jer 7, 5 et sq.). The practice of justice
and the ethos of liberation from before the should include all of the fields of endeavour
state; on the other hand, they anticipated in a mode of living together in solidarity.
the not-yet-realised justice of a coming, The traditional ethos of solidarity of the tribal
universal time of salvation, partly with the peasantry, falling under increasing pres-
help of cosmic representations and images. sure, was appealed to for such a practice, as
The social basis for the critique and hope well as justice and the law which had its
of the prophets was predominantly among foundation beyond the reach of the rulers
the free peasantry, the ‘people of the land’. in the divine Creator and Judge of the earth.
In distinction to the surrounding great They will kiss each other, states Psalm 85.
kingdoms, here there were forms of the A practice of justice in living together and
public sphere that enabled the prophets to adjudication in the case of conflict required
appeal both to the people – for example, at a collective understanding regarding that
public meetings – and to the rulers. This which was just and unjust. What served
democratic dimension was anchored in these ends in the Bible in particular was the
God’s Covenant with the people. Torah, the ‘Instruction’ (misleadingly trans-
Under the pressure of a rising pauper- lated into Latin with ‘lex’). The narrative,
isation and the enslavement of small farmers which was, for the most part, edited during
by their debts in the time of the kings, there the Exile, led the escaped slaves through the
was a massive experience of suffering and desert to Mount Sinai, where Moses received
injustice. The complaints of the Psalms as the Ten Commandments as guidelines for a
well as the lamentations of the prophets free life in the Promised Land. The story is
employed a broad vocabulary which thus a late theological reconstruction that takes
also spoke about justice when the matter up the negative experiences of the times of
explicitly treated was judicial and legal the kings and the prophetic critique. The
measures. It was the prophets, above all, successive collections of commandments and
who considered the structural aspects of laws reflected sociohistorical developments
injustice. The ‘woe’ over the large land- and conflicts of interests (Crüsemann 1992,
owners who added ‘field to field’ (Isaiah 5, 13 et sqq., 21 et sqq.). Thus, for example, the
8) was linked to the ‘woe’ over the civil first version of the Decalogue did not yet
servants who wrote unjust decrees (Isaiah count the ‘field’ of one’s neighbour as one
510, 1 et sq.). The king who built his palace of the objects of forbidden desires (Ex 20,
with ‘injustice’ and did not pay wages was 17). A later version took up the prophetic
sued, in opposition to the king who – also critique of the accumulation of land in the
this was possible – ‘practises justice and hands of great landowners and added ‘field’
righteousness’. ‘Is not this to know me?’ was (Dt 5, 21). This experience was also reflected
God’s question to the King in the text in the legislation for the sabbatical year,
(Jeremiah 22, 13–17) that became fundamental which changed this from a year in which
for Latin-American liberation theology. To the land was left fallow (Ex 23, 10 et sq.) to
the critique of unjust rulers was added – a year of debt cancellation (Dt 15, 1 et sqq.).
close to a class-based analysis – the critique Further developments were reflected in the
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 336

336 • Bastiaan Wielenga, Hermann Klenner and Susanne Lettow

later law for the celebration of the fiftieth the bars of your yoke and made you walk
year (Jubilee), which was supposed to be erect’ (Lev 26, 13). This corresponds to the
celebrated as a year of return to one’s own fact that justice did not appear as an abstract
land (Lev 25 et sqq.; cf. Veerkamp 1993, 91 norm even in legal practice, but as a lib-
et sqq.). eration from injustice. This was the case for
The entire Sabbath legislation anchored the gods just as for humans (Ps 82). In the
in an anticipatory manner the great hope of language of the Psalms, ‘judge me’ is identical
justice in the weekly rhythm of the working with ‘save me’. Therefore, humans and the
day and the day of rest, on which all were world of Creation rejoiced about the
supposed to be equally free and no master prophesised coming of the divine Judge as
or head of the household could demand about an announcement of liberation (Ps
work from dependent women, children, 98, 9, and 76, 9 et sq.; cf. Miranda 1974,
slaves or strangers. Disrupting the patriarchal 113). The critique of injustice not only led
framework, the free peasant was told in the to instructions in the form of historical
commandments that all have the same right narratives, commandments and laws, but
to rest, that ‘your manservant and your also to the articulation of a universal hope
maidservant may rest as well as you’ – in for justice. The ancient oriental association
remembrance of the liberation from slavery of God’s Kingdom with justice in the works
(Dt 5, 13–15). Cow, child-slave and stranger of Creation (e.g. Ps 145) prepared the way
should be able ‘to breathe a sigh of relief’, for the hope of a coming Kingdom of God
as God the Creator did on the seventh day bringing justice on earth. An unknown
(Ex 23, 12 and 31, 17; cf. Wielenga 1988, prophet who lived toward the end of the
130 et sqq.). – The labour movement has time of the Exile (Isaiah 40–55) spoke in lyrical
taken up both ideas: that all should work words of the liberating justice of God that
and that all have a right to rest. The protest would bring salvation to the ends of the
of the churches and unions against the earth. The Creator had not determined the
undermining of Sunday rest can refer back world for chaos (Isaiah 45, 18 et sq.), and his
to this common tradition. suffering servant – be it a single prophet or
The connection of the commandments and the people – would not be discouraged until
laws from the time of the kings and the Exile justice was established across the whole earth
with the expression of God’s Will on Sinai (Isaiah 42, 1 et sqq.).
and the form of the liberator Moses has a In the ‘Torah republic’ (Veerkamp 1993,
fundamental meaning in terms of ideology- 82 et sqq.) of the post-Exile period, this
critique. What was called justice and law all-embracing hope fell at first into the
was therefore not decreed by kings, even if background, while life, according to the pre-
individual kings ‘after God’s heart’, like cepts of the Torah, was moved into the centre
Hezekiah and Josiah, played a role in the of the practice of the faith. That this in no
implementation of reforms to the laws. way, as has often been claimed from a
Established interests have left behind traces, Christian perspective, must lead to petty
but, against the pressure from above, the moralism or legalism is demonstrated, for
right of the poor finds its expression in example, by the intervention of Nehemiah,
the commandments and the laws, thanks to who – supported by a great assembly of the
the remembrance of God’s justice as the people – carried through an historically
event of liberation from slavery which had effective liberation from debt-slavery (Neh
remained alive ‘below’ or was newly re- 5). Together with the Wisdom Literature, the
awakened by the prophets. This is the case, Torah had, at the same time, an important
for example, for the right to asylum anchored significance for personal endeavours to prove
in biblical legislation (cf. Crüsemann 1992, one’s self to be ‘just [tsedaqim]’ and to keep
205 et sqq.). one’s distance from evil-doers. While justice
Divine justice was represented ‘from was primarily related in this Torah-piety to
below’ in Exodus as an empowerment to the way of life (Ps 1, 119), apocalyptic hopes
walk upright proudly: ‘And I have broken of justice, developed from the prophetic
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 337

HKWM – Justice • 337

tradition by scribes (Albertz 1992, Bd. 2, 633 the sick and the imprisoned (Mt 25, 31 et
et sqq.) flared up again and again in times sqq.).
of crisis, particularly among the poor strata. An important reason for the shifting of
the perspective of justice lay in the context
2. Even though the Gospel of the New of the Diaspora. In Galilee, Jesus could
Testament took up the prophetic hope of a propose measures for social praxis (like, for
reign of God, it is conspicuous that the example, the release of debts) that could not
evangelists – except for Matthew – hardly become effective outside of the region
ever use the conceptual vocabulary of justice beyond the personal and communal sphere.
associated with it. That may be connected The scribes endeavoured, as the Talmud
to the fact that the vocabulary of justice proves, to develop legal regulations with the
was possessed by a Torah-piety, aimed at changing economic situation in mind also
cultivating an honest way of living. In the after the fall of Jerusalem (Arye Ben-David
interpretation of the Pharisees, this certainly 1974). However, Synagogue just as Ecclesia
aimed at the sanctification of the whole were confronted in the Diaspora with the
people, but, in reality, it was hardly practic- practical dilemma of only being able to
able for the poor masses. The movement answer structural injustice which led to
around the figure of Jesus with its predo- massive amounts of beggary with organised
minant orientation to the poor and social welfare for the poor, but not with laws.
outsiders expected a social transformation ‘Doing justice’ was even equated in some
in the perspective of the Kingdom of God texts of the Talmud and the New Testament
in which the excluded, treated in the with ‘giving alms’. In this, not only the
meantime as ‘sinners’, would be given their commanded social attitude of the giver was
due. considered, but also the entitlement of the
The scribe-evangelist Matthew made it recipient. Their ‘fundamental right to life’
clear that this in no way must mean an should be materially assured (Kessler 1995,
under-valuing of the Torah, as some Christian 85 et sq.). In the absence of any state-financed
interpreters have believed. The announce- welfare for the poor, the social application
ment of the approaching reign of God was to the begging poor of the commandment
connected to the call to practise the abandon- to love one’s neighbour had a symbolic-
ment of debt-slavery which was commanded critical meaning. The use of the vocabulary
in the Torah, as ‘good news for the poor’ and of justice moved the practice of love onto
as an adequate preparation of the way for the horizon of the expected liberation. ‘Love
the new aeon (Yoder 1972, 34 et sqq.). The is not love without a passion for justice’
difference with the Pharisees (which at (Miranda 1974, 62). Despite its limitedness,
the time of Jesus was necessarily raised welfare for the poor proved itself to be a
in dialogue and only later became un- possibility to anchor in actual deeds the
bridgeable) was related to the question of ideal of a ‘hunger and thirst for justice’ (Mt
whether both dimensions of justice, the 5,6) that had been kept alive by the Torah,
moral and the social, could be simulta- the prophets and Psalms in the Synagogue
neously recognised. The critique went against and Ecclesia, as the Sermon on the Mount
the tendency to limit oneself to details and demonstrated.
to lose sight of the great perspective of justice In the ‘household rules’ of the New
as an instance of transformation (Mt 23, 23). Testament, of course, it also became clear how
The appeal, ‘seek first the kingdom of God life in small diasporic communities, without
and his justice’ was not aimed against the a basis in the land of Israel, soon produced
Pharisees, but against the servants of the a tendency of adaptation and limitation to
‘unjust Mammon’, against the system of personal morality. This, in turn, contributed
injustice that produced endless anxiety (Mt to a conception of justice exclusively as
6, 24 et sqq.). The search for the Kingdom righteousness being moved into the centre
should take place in giving, in sharing with of concerns, justice as the ‘being just’ of the
the hungry, in clothing the naked, in visiting pious or as justification of the single sinner
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 338

338 • Bastiaan Wielenga, Hermann Klenner and Susanne Lettow

in an unchangeable wicked world. The that is, in the ‘body’ of Jesus Christ, ‘there
prophetic and apostolic hope for a socially is neither Jew nor Greek, there is neither
transforming revelation of God’s justice slave nor free, there is neither male nor
disappeared over the horizon. female’ (Gal 3, 28). Where this levelling of
That was certainly not the intention of the relationships of domination and their
apostle Paul, whose authority was used in overcoming became to some extent a reality,
the post-Pauline letters to support a conserv- Paul saw the dawning of a new aeon in
ative social ethos. A predominant mode of which God the all-embracing – ‘ta pánta’ is
reading has interpreted the theology of Paul an apocalyptic keyword in Paul (Taubes
dogmatically and in a depoliticising way on 2004, 36) – will institute his justice (Rom 3,
the basis of the ‘household rules’, until it 21). In this perspective, the uneducated, the
finally could be used ideologically for the weak and the despised were called upon to
legitimation of the powers and forces against ‘shame’ the powerful, the noble and the great
which he had fought (cf. Elliott 1994, 3 et names, as in their meetings ‘in Christ Jesus’
sqq.). Among other causes, this is to be traced the wisdom and justice of God was already
back to the introduction of new elements being realised (1 Cor 1, 26-30). The text from
into the interpretation of Paul by Luther. Jeremiah that is here partly quoted spoke of
Luther certainly rediscovered the liberatory God as he who ‘practises grace, justice, and
meaning of the justice of the Pauline God righteousness on the earth’ (Jer 9, 23 et sq.).
in his stand against the morality of obedience This vision contains the call for a real bodily
of the cloister, but he limited this to the practice of the struggle for justice: ‘Do not
personal relationship to God and restricted yield your members to sin as instruments
the expectation of salvation to the basis of of wickedness, but [. . .] to God as instru-
the justification of the sinner. The Pauline ments of justice’ (Rom 6, 13).
discourse on God’s justice, on the other hand,
turned back to the prophetic-apocalyptic 3. Justice in a feminist perspective – Jewish
traditions that had awaited a transform- and Christian feminist theologians are in
ation which was to be cosmic as well as an agreement that the Bible speaks a patriarchal
intervention into the social. As Käsemann language, assumes gender relations founded
has shown in his exegesis of the program- upon domination, often passes over in silence
matic sentence of the Revelation of God’s the experiences of suffering of women and
justice in Romans (1, 17), the ‘dikaiosúnê toû approves, directly or indirectly, of women’s
theoû’, the ‘justice of God’, is not to be under- legal marginalisation – a fact which has been
stood – in a Greek way – as a legal norm made even worse by patriarchal translations
for God and human, and also not as just and the thought-paradigms of a male-
punishment, but as a forgiving, eschato- dominated history of interpretation. While
logically liberating power and gift which this has prompted some feminists to write
was recognised – in Judaism – as ‘righteous- the Bible off as irredeemable, others have
ness in the relationship of the Covenant’ in set themselves the task of making visible the
faith. It was a matter of a God ‘who brought patriarchal reality in the texts of the Bible
the world back into the purview of his and in the society from which these texts
law’ (1974, 22.26). To that corresponded a emerged. At the same time, they have sought
messianic confrontation with the force and to interrogate the entire perspective of
power of sin, described by Paul also as liberation and justice in the Bible regarding
‘adikía’, ‘injustice’ (Rom 1, 18; 1 Cor 15, 24 its meaning for the women of its time and
et sq.). for women today. Elisabeth Schüssler-
The theological and political key to Fiorenza described this mode of reading as
understanding Paul’s message is the mes- a ‘hermeneutic of suspicion’, with whose
sianic anticipation, the new ‘in Christo’. help the Bible is to be subjected to a
The mode of living together in a new way ‘dialectical process of critical reading and
of the messianic communities was supposed feminist evaluation’ (1988, 13 et sq.). For
to anticipate the expected overcoming of Luise Schottroff, the Bible is the ‘most
social conflicts and unjust relations. ‘There’, important school of justice’, an assessment
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 339

HKWM – Justice • 339

which she holds also to be valid for the all texts with regard to their patriarchal
feminist movement, if current social critique function [. . .] are not mutually exclusive’
and women’s experiences represent the (1994, 182 et sqq.). For the New Testament,
starting-point of interpretation (1994, 11 et Brigitte Kahl brought out how the andro-
sq., 68 et sqq.). Judith Plaskow argued that centric version of the Christian origins
the women’s movement could by all means in Luke can not only be retrospectively
take up the prophetic connection of faith analysed from the viewpoint of a modern
and justice without relinquishing the critical feminism, but also on the basis of the
treatment of its militaristic and patriarchal opening chapter of St Luke’s Gospel itself
image-world: ‘Feminists can affirm our debt (Lk 1), in which the intervention of women
to and continuity with prophetic insistence provides the hermeneutic key for the entire
on connecting faith and justice, even while text: the messianic song of liberation of Mary
we extend the prophets’ social and religious (Lk 1, 55 et sqq.) undermines the patriarchal
critique beyond anything they themselves ‘codes’ of the text. ‘Luke 1 binds the Gospel
envisioned’ (1991, 216 et sqq.). for the poor and the Gospel of/for women
In terms of social history, it can be “genetically” [. . .] together. An “archetype”
assumed that women in biblical times were is established that should be used as
marginalised most strongly in official permanent criterion and criticism of what
religion, legislation and politics. This is also follows’ (1994, 237).
expressed in the texts which relate to these
fields of social endeavour. On the level of 4. Ecological justice. – The pressure of the
the subsistence economy and of the large ecological crises and the charge which makes
family, the men certainly exercised their the biblical ‘dominium terrae’ of Genesis 1
leadership, but the position of women responsible for the readiness to destroy
appeared socially and economically in no nature has strengthened the perception that
way to be so marginal as it is often assumed the biblical understanding of justice as
(cf. e.g. Pr 31 and the remarks of Schwantes righteousness [Gemeinschaftstreue] in
in Tamez 1987, 89 et sqq.). The weakness accordance with the Covenant also included
of women is most clearly formulated in relationships with non-human nature.
the fate of widows, whose protection is Actually, the Bible emphasises the particular
time and again demanded in the biblical role of humans, but this is in the sense that
justice commandments. Crüsemann (1992, this role makes them responsible for the
291 et sqq.) has pointed to a gradual im- protection of creation, or, if they do not fulfill
provement in the legal position of women, their role, condemns them for the destruction
because public jurisdiction limited patriarchal of the relationships of Creation. Rhetoric
rights and brought about greater legal of human ‘dominion’ over the earth and
equality. animals (Gen 1, 28) meant, in that context,
In terms of exegesis, a question would be agriculture, irrigation and the breeding of
to what extent, how and on the basis of what livestock, and was complemented by
social foundation women have insisted upon reference to ‘tilling and keeping’ the garden
such improvement in the name of the (Gen 2, 15). With the animals and the trees,
postulates of justice proclaimed by the ‘Adam’ belonged to ‘adamah’, to the ‘earth’
prophets and the Torah. In fact, there are from which he was taken (Gen 2, 7 and 9).
biblical texts which suggest that women An act of misconduct, which did not do
succeeded in articulating their critique also justice to these relationships, was judged to
inside the biblical canon and to add feminist be a breaking of the Covenant, leading to
criteria to the reading of the Bible. Klara the pollution and the withering away of the
Butting showed with the help of later earth (Isaiah 24, 5).
writings such as Ruth, Esther, Ecclesiastes and This apocalyptic text is related to Noah’s
the Song of Solomon how ‘women enter from Covenant from pre-historical times, described
the margins in the history of the Covenant as a Covenant with the earth and all living
of the Divinity of Israel’ and testify that faith creatures (Gen 9, 9-16). The preceeding para-
in God and the ‘mistrustful examination of digmatic flood-saga, which is also found,
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 340

340 • Bastiaan Wielenga, Hermann Klenner and Susanne Lettow

with different conclusions, in other ancient survival of the human species. God as the
oriental cultures, presented the catastrophe Creator of the human species cannot be
of the flood as a consequence of the violence separated from God the Liberator of the
spreading across the earth. Noah as ‘a Hebrew slaves and Protector of the right of
righteous man’ (Gen 6, 9), that is, as a non- the poor, orphans and widows.
participant in the destruction and violence,
made possible the survival of humans and BIBLIOGRAPHY: R. ALBERTZ, 1992, Religionsgeschichte
animals with the help of the Ark, which Israels in alttestamentlicher Zeit, 2 Vols, Göttingen;
can be regarded as a type of life-saving tech- A. BEN-DAVID, 1974, Talmudische Ökonomie: Die
nology. Jewish commentators saw Noah’s Wirtschaft des jüdischen Palästina zur Zeit der Mischna
justice in his dealing with the different types und des Talmud, Vol. 1, Hildesheim-New York; E.
of animals, only together with whom BLOCH, 1959–79, Gesamtausgabe (GA), Frankfurt/M;
K. BUTTING, 1994, Die Buchstaben werden sich noch
humanity can survive. wundern: Innerbiblische Kritik als Wegweisung
The wide perspective of justice that reveals feministischer Hermeneutik, Berlin; F. CRÜSEMANN,
the connection of social injustice and 1976, ‘Jahwes Gerechtigkeit im Alten Testament’,
ecologically damaging behaviour was based in Ev. Theologie, NF, 31. Jg., Heft 9, 427–50;
upon the declaration of faith in the oneness F. C RÜSEMANN , 1992, Die Tora: Theologie und
of God as the Creator and Liberator. This Sozialgeschichte des alttestamentlichen Gesetzes,
München; W. DIETRICH, 1989, ‘Der rote Faden im
appeared in the conception of justice of the Alten Testament’, in Ev. Theologie, NF, 44. Jg. , Heft
Sabbath-economy, which as an economy of 3, 232–50; U. D UCHROW , 1994, Alternativen zur
‘sufficiency’ and of just sharing made kapitalistischen Weltwirtschaft: Biblische Erinnerung
allowances for both ecological and social und politische Ansätze zur Überwindung einer
needs and functioned as an alternative to lebensbedrohenden Ökonomie, Gütersloh-Mainz; E.
an economy of an uninterrupted accumu- DUSSEL, 1988, Ethics and Community, Maryknoll; N.
ELLIOTT, 1994, Liberating Paul: The Justice of God and
lation. The commandment of rest on the the Politics of the Apostle, Maryknoll; L. EPSZTEIN,
seventh day included livestock. The reason 1986, Social Justice in the Ancient Near East and the
for this day of rest was given as, on the one People of the Bible, London; H. GOLLWITZER, 1988,
hand, the creation (Ex 20, 9-11), and on the ‘Die Revolution des Reiches Gottes und die
other, the liberation from slavery (Dt 5, 14 Gesellschaft’, in H. GOLLWITZER, 1988, Umkehr und
et sqq.). The seventh Sabbath year was Revolution. Aufsätze zu christlichem Glauben und
Marxismus, AW 6, 102–29, München; B. KAHL, 1994,
celebrated both as a year in which the land ‘Toward a Materialist-Feminist Reading’ in ed.
was left fallow and as a year for the can- E. Schüssler-Fiorenza, Searching the Scriptures. A
cellation of debts. The fallow period was Feminist Introduction, 225–40, London; E. KÄSEMANN,
supposed to stand the land in good stead 1974, An die Römer. Handbuch zum Neuen Testament,
just as much as the poor and game (Ex 20, 2nd Edition, Tübingen; R. KESSLER, 1995, ‘Das
10 et sqq.). And, if the Sermon on the Mount Wirtschaftsrecht der Tora’, in eds. K. Füssel,
T. Segbers, . . . so lernen die Völker des Erdkreises
articulated the desire for justice (Mt 5, 1 and Gerechtigkeit. Ein Arbeitsbuch zu Bibel und Ökonomie,
6; 6, 33), it referred for encouragement to 78–94, Luzern-Salzburg; K. KOCH, 1976, ‘Tsedaqah’,
the birds and lilies as an alternative to the in eds. E. Jenni and C. Westermann, Theologisches
orientation toward Solomon, who was Handwörterbuch zum Alten Testament, Vol. 2, 507–30,
regarded in the Bible as the prototype of München-Zürich; P. LEHMANN, 1975, The Trans-
rapacious accumulation (6, 28 et sqq.). figuration of Politics. Jesus Christ and the Question
of Revolution, London; E. LEVINAS, 1998 [1963],
Otherwise than Being or Beyond Essence, tr. A. Lingis,
5. The Bible is neither anthropocentric nor Pittsburgh; J.P. MIRANDA, 1974, Marx and the Bible:
theocentric nor ecocentric, because it is A Critique of the Philosophy of Oppression, Maryknoll;
concerned with the covenant between God, J. PLASKOW, 1991, Standing Again at Sinai: Judaism
humans and all life. Its wish for justice from a Feminist Perspective, San Francisco; G.V.
examines human claims to domination and RAD, 1958, Theologie des Alten Testaments, Vol. 1,
München; L. SCHOTTROFF, 1994, Lydias ungeduldige
at the same time posits the rights to life of Schwestern: Feministische Sozialgeschichte des frü-
the poor and the weak in the centre of hen Christentums, Gütersloh; L. SCHOTTROFF AND
discussion. This main feature divides the M.-T. WACKER, 1999, Kompendium Feministische
biblical tradition from all conceptions Bibelauslegung, Gütersloh; W. SCHOTTROFF, 1999,
prepared to sacrifice the weak for the Gerechtigkeit lernen: Beiträge zur biblischen Sozial-
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 341

HKWM – Justice • 341

geschichte, Gütersloh; E. S CHÜSSLER -F IORENZA , Thus, for example, the concrete behaviour
1988, Brot statt Steine: Die Herausforderung einer of a human or their general mode of
feministischen Interpretation der Bibel, Freiburg/ behaviour, the judgement of a court, the law
Switzerland; F. SEGBERS, 1999, Die Hausordnung der
Tora, Luzern; D. SÖLLE (ed.), 1994, Für Gerechtigkeit
or the bill before parliament, the war
streiten: Theologie im Alltag einer bedrohten Welt, of a state, the practice of the police, the
Gütersloh; E. T AMEZ , 1987, Against Machismo: property relations and the hierarchies in a
Interviews, Oak Park/Ill; J. TAUBES, 2004 (1987), The society, the relation of ethnic groups and of
Political Theology of Paul, tr. Donna Hollander, Palo the genders to each others and of the state
Alto; T. VEERKAMP, 1993, Autonomie und Egalität: to them, the death penalty, racism, the
Ökonomie, Politik und Ideologie in der Schrift, Berlin;
B. WIELENGA, 1988, It’s a Long Road to Freedom,
censorship of a teacher, income tax, the
Madurai; B. WIELENGA, 1999, Toward an Eco-Just privilege of education and even fate, the way
Society, Bangalore; J.H. YODER, 1972, The Politics of of the world or the characteristics of real,
Jesus, Grand Rapids. imaginary or made-up beings, are assessed
as just (or unjust). Such an assessment means
also either a positive or negative judgement,
Bastiaan Wielenga either an approval or disapproval, appre-
Translated by Peter Thomas ciation or a condemnation. A standard gauge
for the judgment of a behaviour as just or
Armut/Reichtum, Aufstand, Ausbeutung, Bauern- unjust can be both really existing and also
krieg, Befreiung, Christen für den Sozialismus, merely imagined relations in the form of
Christlicher Sozialismus, Eingedenken, feministische conceptions, goals or ideals. Negative
Theologie, Gemeinde christliche, Geschlechter- judgement implies the demand to suppress
verhältnisse, Gewissen, Glauben, Gott, Göttin, mate- unjust behaviour and to replace unjust
rialistische Bibellektüre, Messianismus, Naturrecht, relations with just ones.
Naturschutz, religiöse Revolutionsbewegungen, Justice and injustice are mobilising
religiöser Sozialismus, Revolution, Urchristentum, concepts: in emancipatory movements for
utopischer Sozialismus. political, social, cultural, ethnic, national,
and international or gender justice, they
Christians for socialism, Christian socialism,
motivate the excluded, the exploited, the
congregation/parish, conscience, exploitation, faith,
underprivileged and the oppressed to reform
feminist theology, gender relations, God, goddess,
or revolutionise the social relations which
insurrection/uprising, liberation, materialist reading
are held to be unjust. With the help of de-
of the Bible, messianism, natural law, peasant war,
mands for justice, however, also counter-
poverty/wealth, primitive Christianity, protection of
revolutions and wars can also be incited.
nature, religious revolutionary movements, religious
The use and misuse of versions of justice
socialism, reminiscence, revolution, utopian socialism.
are at times difficult to differentiate.

II. Justice/Injustice – ‘Justice’, ‘just’ and ‘law’ 1. The views of humans regarding what is
(Greek: dikaiosúnê, díkaios, díkê; Latin: iustitia, just and what is unjust are embedded in
iustus, ius) are among the most popular their individually and socially conditioned
words in speech and writing and, at the structure of interests which reflect such views
same time, among the most contested and upon which they at the same time exert
concepts. Constituting the valid measure for an influence. Therefore a binary code of
the assessment of patterns of behaviours humanity of ‘justice/injustice’ is only able
and relations, ‘justice’ and ‘just’ as well as to be universally accepted at the price of its
‘injustice’ and ‘unjust’ are words of everday, lack of content. However, there is a timeless
political and scientific language, particularly valid measure of correct, that is, just,
of theologians, philosophers, sociologists behaviour of all and for all in the kingdom
and lawyers. – With the concepts ‘justice’ or of utopias and illusions. No definition of
‘injustice’, the relations between at least two justice, but above all, no criterion of justice
actions or conditions together with their has yet proved to be immune to contra-
authors are assessed, which then serves as dictions or even refutation. Hegel’s verdict
a standard for other actions and conditions. is valid for many ideas of justice: ‘This
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 342

342 • Bastiaan Wielenga, Hermann Klenner and Susanne Lettow

grandiose talk of the best of humanity [. . .] of the polis. Politics and the art of living
such ideal essence and goals collapse as well were combined in a justice that was
empty words which edify the heart and leave practised. This made Democritus, the teacher
reason empty. They uplift [erbauen] but do of chance and the founder of atomism, at
not build [aufbauen]’ (PS, §390). Brecht, the same time the first theoretician of
coming to terms with experiences, noted conscience. Like Socrates (cf. Grg, Crito),
that ‘There are states in which justice is Democritus could therefore say: ‘Who
highly praised. In such states, one can commits injustice is worse for having done
suppose, it is particularly difficult to practise it/unhappier than who suffers justice’ –
justice’ (GA 18, 53). ‘ho adikôn toû adikouménou kakodaimo-
Nonetheless, demands for justice as means nésteros’ (Frg 45). – In the context of his
for the critique of social relations which are socially conservative idea (not a utopia!) of
judged to be unjust have always worked to a state divided into three classes with a rigid
mobilise, to demand progress, and also division of labour in addition to slavery,
occasionally to hinder progress. Justice has Plato, the arch-enemy of the democratic
helped to keep alive a critical distance materialist, characterised justice with the
between reality and ideality, between legality formula ‘tà autoû práttein’, which obliged
and legitimacy, between is and ought, each to fulfil their class-specific function and
between that which has been achieved and not to interfere in anything which was not
that which can be achieved. Aristotle had their business. It is just when each has their
already registered that justice, just as equality, own and does their own thing (Republic,
was demanded above all by the weaker (Pol 433a) as well as receives relatively the same
1318b). Just as justice without law proved (Laws, 757). This trinitary formula of justice
to be powerless, so law without justice as a measure of having, doing and receiving
proved to be tyrannical. is subordinated to a conception of a state
whose ruler certainly wisely obeyed the law
2. Theories of justice in Europe can only be (Laws, 715), but who was allowed to use lies
spoken of since Democritus, Plato and and deception for the benefit of those who
Aristotle. More than a thousand years were ruled (Republic, 459).
previously in the most important legal The theory of justice of antiquity with the
document of oriental antiquity, the Baby- most consequences was that of Aristotle.
lonian king Hammurapi (1728–1686 B.C.E.) Justice was ‘political’ in the sense of ‘being
had claimed to have been called by the Gods appropriate for the polis’, ‘he dè dikaiosúnê
‘to win recognition in the land for justice’. politikón’, because justice [díkê] was the order
In the Hebrew Bible (8th to 2nd centuries [táxsis] of the political community and
B.C.E.) the word justice [sadaqa], appearing judgement [krísis] about the just (Pol I,
523 times, had described in the most 1253a38). Humans were political beings
comprehensive way the world and human living in accordance with nature in com-
order ordained by God (Monz 1995, 63 et munity; they had a share in the distinction
sqq.). In Homer’s and Hesiod’s epics, justice of the useful/the harmful [sumphéron/
was not distinguished from law, the goddess b l a b e ró n ] a n d o f t h e j u s t / t h e u n j u s t
of law and order, Themis and Dike, or the [díkaion/ádikon] (Pol I, 1253 a18). ‘Justice’ was
decisions of the rulers acting according to ‘expressed in many different ways [pleonachôs
divine decree (Odyssey 3, 133; Iliad 2, 206; légesthai]’ (EN V, 1129a23–31): on the one
Works and Days 248–85). And a stronger hand, ‘justice’ was called ‘the perfected
accusation of the ruling injustice is hardly virtue/competence in relation to others’,
more imaginable than Hesiod’s, which ‘aretê teleía pròs héteron’ (1129b26 et sq., in
exposed it as the injustice of the rulers, for a similar vein, 1130a4), that is, it is the social
which he introduced the concept of the deployment of all attitudes to be gained by
‘devourers of gifts’, the ‘dôrophágoi’. experience and education and all attitudes
Democritus, the democrat amongst the prescribed by the law [nómos] (1129b19–27;
classical Greek philosophers, thought justice similarly, 1130 b25 et sqq.). In addition to
as a horizontal relationship between citizens this comprehensive meaning of justice, in
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 343

HKWM – Justice • 343

the fifth book of the Nicomachean Ethics need/necessity [chreía] justified the intro-
Aristotle gave a presentation en mérei, that duction of an artificial [ex hupothéseôs] means
is, a presentation of different partial forms as a measure in order to make commodities
of justice (1130b16), whose definition he for exchange equivalent [íson] (b20 et sq).
developed from the injustices which were Without exchange, however, no community
remedied or avoided by these partial justices: [koinônía] was possible (b17). The means
the ‘equal [íson]’ as a balancing of the which here put things right was money,
‘unequal [ánison]’ was the predominant nómisma (b21). An orientation toward use-
determination (1130b7). ‘Equal’, however, is value and the establishment of community
not to be understood in egalitarian terms, were for Aristotle the measure of just
but, rather, in the context of a hierarchy; it exchange and trade in accordance with
is not the persons but, rather, their inequality, nature (Pol I, 1257a16). The deployment of
which has a claim to equality: that which is money for its increase, however, be it by
fitting to a person had to correspond to their means of profit-oriented trade or by the
‘dignity’. Among these are two differentiated payment of interest, which allowed ‘money
concepts of justice specific to their field: the [to come forth] from money’, was regarded
first, the concept of a ‘justice of distribution by him to be unnatural (1257b28–58a10).
[dianemêtikón or nemêtikòn díkaion, 1132b24]’ It was, among other elements, the
oriented to the distribution of honours, realisation that commodities must first be
offices and goods [dianomaîs timês ê chrêmátôn, made commensurable in order to be
1130b31] and that justice which ordered exchangeable which caused Marx to praise
contractual intercourse, ‘en toîs sunallágmasi the genius of Aristotle, because he had
diorthôtikón’ (1131a1; 1132b24f). The latter discovered a relation of equality in the
divided, in its turn, into two further concepts: expression of value of commodities, even
the first, that of the justice of exchange, if he was not able to read out from the
regulated by ‘voluntary’ transactions, commodity-form the fact that it is human
precisely, market dealings of all types; the labours which are expressed in it as equally
other, that of the repayment of injuries valid. Marx explained that this limitation of
which compensated the consequences of knowledge was due to the fact that Greek
‘involuntary’ transactions in the form of society was founded upon slave labour, that
reparation or vengeance [talion] (1131a1–9), is, upon the inequality of humans and their
that is, such actions which in the modern labour-powers (MECW 35, 69; regarding EN,
state are covered by criminal law. 1133b). – Actually, for Aristotle, there was
Common to all these partial justices is a legal relation between slaves and their
that their centre, in accordance with the masters only in a metaphorical way [katà
Democritean formula, is a middle point metaphorán]. He named this legal relation
between a ‘too much’ and a ‘too little’, a ‘díkaioin despotikón’ and compared it to the
type of equality in the sense of equilibrium. law of the rational [lógon échon] part of the
In the justice of distribution, it was a matter soul [psychê] opposed to the irrational or
of a ‘geometrical’ equality, for the offices and speechless [álogon] part (EN V, 1138b5–9). To
honours of the polis should be awarded to the extent that the slave was a human and
the members of the polis in proportion to had a share in law [nómos] and contract
their competence and education. In the [sunthêkê], there could be justice and also
justice of exchange, on the other hand, it friendship for him; to the extent that he was
was superficially a matter of a numerical, a slave, that is, a mere tool [órganon], there
arithmetical equality; though, even here, was not (EN VIII, 1161b2–6). Even his foot
proportionality had to be established had no right compared to the master (Magna
(Haacke 1994, 44). The commodities which moralia, 1194b). The law between man and
were exchanged for each other were as woman followed from the aristocratic
different as the competence and with that principle of ‘kat’ aretên’: to each of them
also the rank of their producers; a bed and was given that which was appropriate to
a house, for example, are not commen- them, ‘tò harmózon hekástô’ (EN VIII,
surable, ‘súmmetra’ (EN V, 1133b19). Only 1161a23–5). It was just that, in the marital
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 344

344 • Bastiaan Wielenga, Hermann Klenner and Susanne Lettow

relation, the man ruled over the women. The what harmed them, they would be obliged
reverse would be against nature for Aristotle to the corresponding commandments and
(Pol, 1259b1–3). proscriptions. A law that became unjust
The understanding of justice which had to the needs of the community would not
already appeared in Plato (Republic, 331; have the nature of law and would therefore
Laws, 757) and Aristotle (EN, 1131a–b), and lack the validity of law. With that, the concept
which occupied the position which for the of justice was materialised, relativised and
Romans was assigned to the principle of historicised. The birthplace of justice was
‘suum cuique’, ‘to each their own’, reached not in the hereafter, but in the here and now,
its final form, via Cicero (De legibus I, 6, 19), in the needs of humans, changing in time
in the version which the jurist Ulpian (circa and with place.
170–223) gave to it. This occurred in the The adherents of the Stoa who argued
work of codification under the Eastern against Epicurus transferred the versions of
Roman Caesar Justinian (compiled between justice tailor-made to the polis, the ancient
527 and 534, and since 1583 denoted with Greek city-state, to a conception of justice
Corpus iuris civilis). From this work has been which was aimed at the cosmopolis, at a world
handed down a quotation which even today order. From that emerged the triad which
continues to be used often, though, of course, was typical for the Stoics and which exerts
often misunderstood: ‘Iustitia est constans an effect right up to the present day: human
et perpetua voluntas ius suum tribunes’ law – natural law – world law. The ‘lex
(Initial sentence of the Institutions, also called humana’ was overlaid by a ‘lex naturalis’
the Digests, 1, 1, 10: ‘Justice is the unwavering and this, in its turn, was overlaid by a ‘lex
and enduring will to give to each their right’), aeterna’ (Chrysippos, De lege aeterna, 325;
a conservative legal norm which guarantees Cicero, De re publica, III, 22). What was just
the existing property relations. Cicero’s and unjust derived not from the satisfaction
presentation (De officiis II, 21, 73) logically or non-satisfaction of earthly needs, but from
follows: in the first instance, one who the obedience to or revolt against an order
manages the community would have to see of things pretending to be divine. The
that each one would maintain their level of monopoly on definition and interpretation
property and a reduction in the wealth of of the rulers ensured that such a conception
private persons, not through the intervention of justice reflected their interests.
of the state, would be brought about.
It was Epicurus who removed justice from 3. The Patristics and Scholastics less
a transcendent perspective. He continued systematised the many and diverse and also
the contract theory that had been developed contradictory ideas of justice of the Old and
in the milieu of Protagoras (believed by some New Testaments than integrated these ideas,
to have been a student of Democritus). There including the Aristotelian world-view, into
is no justice in itself, only as a contract an understanding suited to the papal church,
[sunthêkê, súmbolon] between humans living the state and world domination. The great
together. In order to define the fundamental phrase of Augustine, ‘What are kingdoms
principle of such a contract as ‘just by nature’, if they are lacking justice than great bands
‘tês phúseôs díkaion’ (Ratae sententiae, 33), of robbers?’ (De civitate dei, IV, 4: Remota
he chose the proven formula ‘not to harm itaque justitia, quid sunt regna, nisi magna
[each other] and not to allow each other to latrocinia?), together with his other maxim,
be harmed’, ‘mê bláptein mêdè bláptesthai’ ‘There is only true justice in the community
(Rs 33, excerpted by Marx in MEGA IV.1, whose founder and ruler is Jesus Christ’ (II,
16, 603). By conceiving natural law as a law 21), took a turn which was also oriented
appropriate to human nature in place [tópos] toward both internal and external sanctions.
and time, Epicurus freed justice from being The reversal of Protagoras’s saying, ‘man
a canon of virtue predetermined by God or is the measure of all things, of their being
dressed-up in any other mystical way. If how they are, of their not being how they
the community of members of the polis are not’ (qtd in Plato, Tht, 151 et sq.), into
recognised what was useful to them and the opposed formula of Plato according to
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 345

HKWM – Justice • 345

which God is the measure of all things (Laws allegiance on the grounds that there is no
IV, 716c) (which passed into Latin as ‘non salvation of the soul outside of the Roman
sub homine, sed sub Deo et sub lege!’), Catholic Church [unam sanctam catholicam et
belonged to the intellectual preconditions of Apostolicam ecclesiam, extra quam nulla est
the Christian mode of deriving the relation salus].
between the divine, the natural and human
law, of ‘lex divina’, ‘lex naturalis’ and ‘lex 4. Christianity has thus certainly been
humana’. Following that was the law which increasingly instrumentalised by the rulers
was valued more highly at the time of the since the time of Constantine I (from 306
standard of justice for the inferior law. Each Roman Caesar in Byzantium). But Christian
‘lex lata’ just as each ‘lex ferenda’ was subject belief is innately no invention of those in
to the standard of judgement, and thus also power to justify their exercise of violence
to a standard of condemnation, of a natural both internally and externally, no purposive
law derived from the order of the Creation. invention of the ruling against the oppressed
Its content had been equated with the social classes. The early Christian verses on
regulations of the Old and the New Testaments justice cannot fairly be understood as an
by the Decretum Gratiani (circa 1140), even- ideology designed for the legitimation of
tually the first part of the later Corpus iuris war and colonisation, even if they were used
canonici (official since 1580) (I, 1: Ius natu- as such for hundreds of years. With their
rale est quod in lege et in Evangelio continetur). help established legality has been legiti-
St. Thomas of Aquinas denied a self- mated, yet has also been delegitimated. With
legitimation of right and law: Any ‘lex Christian verses about justice and injustice,
humana’ which did not agree with ‘lex the disciplining of the lower orders by the
naturalis’ (which, for its part, had its ground higher has certainly been further entrenched
of validity in ‘lex divina’) is no law, but, in the course of history. For example, the
rather, a ‘legis corruptio’ (Summa theologica, following sentences of Paul: ‘Let every soul
II–I, qu. 95, 2). be subject unto the higher powers. For there
The earthly consequences of the above is no power but of God’ (Rom 13, 1);
conception of justice derived from the ‘Servants, be obedient to them that are your
participation of humans in the unfathomable masters [. . .] with fear and trembling’ (Eph
will of God were marked by the power/ 6, 5); ‘Wives, submit yourselves unto your
powerlessness structure of feudal society own husbands, as unto the Lord’ (5, 22).
and the claim of the Roman Church, with At the same time, the reigning power/
its head as Vicarius Dei on earth, to interpret powerlessness structure was undermined
divine right in the last instance. With the by verses concerning justice in the New
principle of justice of ‘to each their own’, St Testament whose content can be interpreted
Thomas justified slavery and serfdom (S.th., in an opposed direction. For example: ‘Who
I, qu. 21; II–II, 57), and he gave the argument believes in Christ is just’ (Rom 10, 4); ‘Bear
of equality as a reason for why heretics ye one another’s burdens, and so fulfill the
should be excommunicated and burnt as law of Christ’ (Gal 6, 2); ‘If any would not
believers in falsity (II–II, 11: non solum ab work, neither should they eat’ (2 Thess 3,
ecclesia per excommunicationem separari, sed 10); ‘He hath put down the mighty from
etiam per mortem a mundo excludi), just as the their seats, and exalted them of low degree’
authorities also justly killed the counterfeiter. (Lk 1, 52). From its origins onward, Christ-
With his Bull Divino amore of the 18 June ianity, like other religions, has also reflected
1452, Pope Nicholas V enabled the King of the longings and visions of the simple
Portugal to conquer the lands of the non- people, their illusory happiness (MECW 1,
believers and to force their inhabitants into 149; MECW 3, 175).
eternal servitude [in perpetuum servitutem]. It has been made manifest time and time
And with his Bull Regnans in excelsis of the again that opposed interests can hide behind
25 February 1570, Pope Pius V dismissed the representations of justice of the biblical
Queen Elizabeth of England, at the same books – thus, in the sixteenth century, the
time releasing her subjects from her oath of pamphlets of the rebelling peasants partly
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 346

346 • Bastiaan Wielenga, Hermann Klenner and Susanne Lettow

used the same biblical passages as the 5. It was the great service of the European
sermonising priests of their opponents well Enlightenment from Hobbes, to Rousseau,
disposed to the nobility (Laube/Seiffert 1978, to Hegel, to have initiated the universal-
26, 316). Acts of the Apostles 4, 32 was tortured isation of a rationally worked-out terrestrial
out of Thomas Müntzer as a confession understanding of justice. Since the laws of
under duress (508): ‘And the multitude of this world were not made in an other-
them that believed were of one heart and of worldly realm, justice also, as a measure
one soul: neither said any of them that ought of correspondence between the actually
of the things which he possessed was his valid and the really required law (between
own; but they had all things common’ (In existence and reality), was to be found
the Vulgate: ‘multitudinis autem credentium nowhere else than in the here and now. Not
erat cor et anima una, nec quisquam eorum, the revelation of a God, but the reason of
quae possidebant, aliquid suum esse dicebat, humans was the means of argumentation;
sed erant illis omnia communia’). Just ten human rights were invoked as a measure of
years before, the pious Thomas More had law from heaven at the most metaphorically.
written in the first book of his Utopia that Hobbes, explicitly repudiating Aristotle,
private property and justice exclude each Thomas and Suárez, and turning instead to
other: ‘I don’t see how you can ever get the tradition of the materialists Epicurus
any real justice, so long as there’s private (Ratae sententiae, 31–8) and Bacon (Treatise
property’ (65). In England’s revolution of the on Universal Justice, Aph. 1–7), revolutionised
seventeenth century, the eloquent Gerrard the traditional connection of derivation of
Winstanley published his pamphlets, among ‘pseudo-philosophical’ scholasticism between
them The New Law of Righteousness (London natural law legitimated by divine law and
1649), with which he called to take away the the law of humans by turning it the right
monopoly of access to God from the priests, way up. Natural law [das Naturrecht, ius
the land from the landowner, the law from naturale] is nothing other than the original
the lawyers and the authority of the state freedom of every human, their own power
from those who possessed it. His maxim, to act according to their wishes, which must
the ‘Law of Righteousnesse in the pure therefore be overcome. Otherwise the life
light of Reason’, was based exclusively on of humans remains ‘solitary, poor, nasty,
quotations from the Bible. In France’s brutish, and short’. Only when humans
revolution of the eighteenth century, it was recognise their interests by means of their
two priests, the abbot Henri Grégoire and reason could there emerge a legal system
the curate Jacques Roux, who were among suitable for civil society [bürgerliche
the sharpest critics of feudal society, but also, Gesellschaft] that would be the opposite of
already, of bourgeois society. Roux expressly a war ‘of every man against every man’
equated justice with the rights of man, but (Leviathan, Ch. XIII). – John Locke held that
declared that freedom, just as equality, was it was impossible that the rulers of the earth
an empty delusion so long as one class of could derive even the least shadow of
humans could starve out another (147, 173). authority out of that which they were wont
In the Germany of the nineteenth century, to regard, by means of biblically handed-
Wilhelm Weitling regarded ‘to be rich’ to down revelation, as the source of their power.
be a synonym for ‘to be unjust’ (Die Mensch- Justice, that is, assumed that an elected
heit, wie sie ist und wie sie sein sollte, qtd in parliament decided according to publicly
Kowalski 1962, 212). In The Poor Sinner’s stated laws and by means of authorised
Gospel of 1845, he compared justice with the judges on the rights of subjects, since these
community of property and opposed it to had, after all, only united in a society in
private property with reference to Lk 14, 33 order to protect themselves and their
(‘whosoever he be of you that forsaketh not property (Of Government, II, 136–9). – David
all that he hath, he cannot be my disciple’) Hume declared: ‘justice takes its rise from
and a dozen further quotations from the human conventions’ (Of Human Nature, III,
Bible (86 et sqq.). 2). Justice, just like property, had its origin
exclusively in general utility.
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 347

HKWM – Justice • 347

The emancipation of the legal system from would be exercised by co-ordinated mutually
a Christian/ecclesiastical standard was a interdependent controlling organs (De l’Esprit
part of the process of self-clarification of all des Lois, XI, 6). Rousseau, on the other hand,
anti-feudal classes concerning their interests favoured the identity of the governing and
and their opponents. Against the influence the governed, which excluded unjust laws
of the three Christian churches on the social because nobody could be unjust toward
and legal system, von Pufendorf insisted themself (Du contrat social, II, 6). For his part,
that there was just as little a Christian natural Kant put the touchstone for the justice of a
law as a Christian surgery (Eris scandica). law in the idea of reason of obliging ‘every
Kant allowed neither religion nor morality law giver that they so write their laws as if
to assume the throne of critique, but only they could arise from the united will of the
autonomous human Reason purified by entire people’ (On the Proverbial Saying, WA
self-critique. He did not approve, however, 11, 153). All of that was, at least, thought in
of the ‘uncouth appeal to supposedly an anti-feudal sense and in the direction of
conflicting experience’ which would not even a civil society [bürgerliche Gesellschaft]. Hegel,
exist if one had judged at the appropriate of course, undermined their claims to
time according to reasonable ideas (WA 3, absoluteness with his theory that this ‘civil
324; 11, 129). society [bürgerliche Gesellschaft]’, by the
The rejection of God as the source of contradiction immanent to it between an
justice, however, was not supposed to result, excess of wealth on the one side and poverty
for example, in the declaration of justice as on the other, would ‘be driven beyond itself’
trivial, or free manoeuvre being given to (PR, § 246; cf. MECW 6, 504, where bourgeois
human arbitrariness. To claim that there was relations of production ‘outstrip themselves’).
no right or wrong except that which the laws In the development of versions of justice
ordered or forbade was, for Montesquieu, tending toward socialism before Marx and
tantamount to the claim that the radii would Engels, the question of property played
not have been the same before the first circle a central role. Rousseau, certainly no social-
was drawn (De l’Esprit des Lois, I, 1). It was ist, was absolutely clear that inequalities
much more a case of the objectivity of a and conflicts of interests were among the
criterion of justice. Hegel radicalised the inevitable effects of property (Discours sur
problem by denying any scientific meaning l’inégalité, 209). This was the reason why he
to former modes of treating natural right, counted among the preconditions of civic
the apriori as well as the empirical, and by freedom not only equality before the law,
refusing to concede the possibility of but also equality of wealth, at least to the
existence of a perfect legal system with total extent that nobody should be so rich as to
justice (W 2, 437, 485 et sqq.). On the one be able to buy another person, and nobody
hand, hundred years’ old law justly went so poor, as to have to sell themselves (Du
down if the basis which was the condition contrat social, II, 11). The feminist Mary
of its existence was no longer valid (W 4, Wollstonecraft saw in freedom a beautiful
508), and, on the other hand, that which was idea never realised, because ‘the demon of
only supposed to be, without actually being, property has ever been at hand, to encroach
had absolutely no truth (W 3, 192). [upon] the sacred rights of men, and to fence
The philosophers of the Enlightenment round with awful pomp that war with
did not content themselves with disquali- justice’ (1790, 14). William Godwin (1793)
fying traditional law as unjust by a verdict indeed characterised reason as an important
of critical reason. Their actual concern was instrument of justice, but did not overlook
a society in which law and justice tended the fact that the rich had a monopoly of state
to coincide. How that was to be managed violence and transformed the legal system
was a matter of dispute among them. into an instrument of oppression over the
Montesquieu hoped for a constitution of poor, thus hindering justice (1976, 91 and
freedom and justice in which the three types 790).
of ways in which the state exercised power At the same time the murmuring tenden-
(la puissance législative, exécutrice, de juger) cies which had been around for centuries of
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 348

348 • Bastiaan Wielenga, Hermann Klenner and Susanne Lettow

a ‘Christianity from below’ began to be absolute legal principle’ (Werke, 435). The
amplified. Thus Saint-Simon demanded in Hessische Landbote (Hessian Land Herald) of
his dialogue New Christianity to arrange 1834 that he helped to write had charac-
society according to the principle of neigh- terised the judiciary [die Justiz] as a ‘whore
bourly love (Rom 13, 9; cf. already Lev 14, 18) of the German princes’. Simultaneously, it
and to turn proletarians into partners had stated that the people had been robbed
enjoying equal rights (400 et sqq.). Étienne of the rights of man and citizen, and ended
Cabet radicalised his understanding of with the yearning for a ‘kingdom of justice.
Christianity in the form of a Communist Amen’ (365).
Confession of Faith (in Höppner, Vol. 2,
392–407). Weitling wrote in a manuscript 6. Probably the earliest use of the word
(published for the first time in 1929!) with justice in the oeuvre of Marx and Engels
the title Justice that, among all established (except for excerpts) comes from Engels in
principles, only the Christian led to a ‘satis- October 1843: ‘Show them that real liberty
fying definition of the concept of justice’ and real equality will be only possible under
(123). Karl Schapper, member of the League community arrangements, show them that
of the Proscribed, later of the League of the Just justice demands such arrangements, and
(!), saw in community property that which then you will have them all on your side’
Christ had actually wanted, and was of the (MECW 3, 397). The most likely last use of
opinion – at any rate, in 1838 – that one the word justice is also by Engels, who, in
‘could draw the most for our principles from, 1891, ironically characterised the kingdom
and have the best effect on the people with, of God on earth, translated into philosophical
Christ’s teachings’ (qtd in Förder, 105). terms, as a place ‘where the eternal truth
Finally, ‘the rights of man’, as they had and justice is realised or should be realised’
been catalogued in different versions in (MECW 27, 191). In a letter of June 1879,
France’s Great Revolution as foundations of he criticised the ethical socialism of Karl
the Constitution (cf. Klenner 1982, 226–41), Höchberg and ‘his programme of the
had served as a criterion for judgement and “Zukunft”, according to which socialism was
condemnation of the social relations which to arise out of the concept of “justice”. Such
were to be revolutionised. In Article 4 of her a programme directly excluded from the
Declaration of the Rights of Woman and the outset all those who ultimately regarded
Female Citizen of 1791, Olympe De Gouges socialism, not as the logical outcome of any
had regarded as a consequence of ‘justice’ idea or principle such as justice, etc., but as
that women were given back their ‘natural the ideal product of a material-economic
right’ to equal rights (qtd in Schröder, 37). process, of the social process of production
Mary Wollstonecraft denied the existence at a given stage’ (MECW 45, 362 et sqq.).
of a ‘divine right of husbands’ no less than With these three selected remarks, the
that of a ‘divine right of kings’ (1790, 122). range of the versions of justice of Marx and
‘Inequality and oppression are synonymous’, Engels becomes immediately clear. Initially,
Babeuf and Buonarroti had both recognised the doubled identification of justice with real
(qtd in Höppner, Bd. 2, 97). From the Société freedom and equality, on the one hand, but
des droits de l’homme to the Society of the Rights also, on the other hand, the identification of
of Man and the League of the Proscribed, to German philosophy, which via detours has
the League of the Just (according to its statutes: finally arrived at communism, with the
the League of Justice!), the forerunner of the concerns of French, English and German
League of the Communists, the realisation of socialists from Babeuf to Proudhon to
the rights of man and of the citizen was Weitling (MEGA I.3, 495 et sqq.). In a final
named as the political goal of the illegal move, justice was declared to be unsuitable
organisations inclined toward communism for helping to found a programme for
as well as the labour movement (cf. Ramm, socialism.
6; Klenner, 257; Förder, 93). That corres- In the complex understanding of justice
ponded to the view of Georg Büchner that of Marx and Engels at least five aspects can
‘in social things [one must] depart from an be differentiated:
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 349

HKWM – Justice • 349

6.1. As dialecticians, Marx and Engels re- existing economic relations, at times from
fused to elevate the historical explanation the conservative side, at times from the
for the coming into being of a situation into revolutionary side’ (MECW 23, 359). Thus
the standard of a justification for the con- the philosophers of the Enlightenment had
tinuance of this situation, as Savigny and announced that they wanted to liberate all
his historical school of law had done (MECW of humanity from the former social states of
1, 203; MECW 3, 177). As historical material- superstition and oppression, and to introduce
ists, besides an empirically pre-determined, a kingdom of reason in which would reign,
self-legitimating legality, they also rejected beside the eternal truth and the inalienable
an apriori ascertainable, eternal justice rights of man, also ‘eternal justice’. This had,
shaping (or which was supposed to shape) then, of course, turned out to be ‘the ideal-
all humans at all times and in all situations. ised kingdom of the bourgeoisie’, with
Particularly in his conflicts with Proudhon, bourgeois justice, equality at the most before
Marx conducted a vitriolic polemic against (but not under) the law and private property
all attempts to derive revolutionary demands as a human right (AD, MECW 25, 19). As it
from considerations of justice. The ‘inspir- turned out that the opposition of exploiter
ation of eternal justice’ (Poverty of Philosophy, and exploited, of rich idlers and working
MECW 6, 193), according to Marx, reflected poor had remained, communist utopians
civil society [bürgerliche Gesellschaft] itself as would have wanted in their turn to free
an ideal, which was the reason why it was immediately all of humanity and to intro-
hopeless ‘to want to reconstitute society on duce the ‘kingdom of reason and eternal
the basis of what is merely an embellished justice’, an ‘eclectic average socialism’ as an
shadow of the actual world’ (MECW 6, 144, expression of ‘absolute truth, reason and
trans. modified; commentated on by Engels justice’ (19 et sqq.). Also here ideas of justice
in MECW 26, 283). Proudhon drew ‘his ideal were regarded as necessary, even if illusory
of justice, of justice éternelle, from the legal reflections of historical events, particularly
relations which correspond to commodity in the consciousness of everyday life.
production, as a result of which [. . .] the
proof which is for all petit bourgeois so 6.3. In a polemic with the English banker
comforting is also provided, namely, that and economist James Gilbart, who had
the form of commodity production is just named the profit-seeking of those who
as eternal as justice. [. . .] Does one know loaned money a ‘self-evident principle of
anything more of, for example, usury, if one natural justice’ (MECW 37, 337), Marx
says, it contradicts “justice éternelle” [. . .]?’ declared that the assumption of a ‘natural
(MECW 35, 94 et sqq.; trans. modified). To justice’ in this context was ‘nonsense’ (ibid.).
destroy the normative aura of an eternal However, Engels differentiated between
justice together with its metaphysical basis ‘what is morally fair, what is even fair in
was a life-long element of Marx’s and law’ from what is ‘socially fair’ (MECW 24,
Engels’s ideology-critical modus operandi. 376). By ‘fair in law’ he understood a
Intuition provided them with no certainty behaviour or relation corresponding to the
of judgement. To judge or condemn some- currently valid juridical laws, which was
thing without having comprehended it was thus legally just. By ‘socially fair’ (MECW
anathema for them (MECW 35, 503). 24, 376) he understood a behaviour or
relation corresponding to the current mode
6.2. Even if Marx and Engels radically of production, which was thus economically
rejected the existence of an ahistorical and just. He therefore suggested replacing the
transcendental – that is, absolute – justice, long-standing slogan of the English labour
they nevertheless acknowledged the his- movement, ‘A fair day’s wages for a fair
torical (that is, temporary) inevitability of day’s work!’ with ‘Possession of the means
ideas of justice as well as the necessity of of work by the working people themselves!’
uncovering the material basis of these ideas. (MECW 24, 378). And Marx held legal
The ideal of ‘eternal justice’ was, for Engels, contracts about economic transactions as
‘the ideologised, glorified expression of the actions freely entered into by the participants
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 350

350 • Bastiaan Wielenga, Hermann Klenner and Susanne Lettow

to be just, provided that they corresponded production (MECW 37, 762) or ‘historical
to the current mode of production, and held justice’ (MECW 16, 395). The general course
them to be unjust as soon as they were of history thus appeared as the judge of that
inadequate for the mode of production; which was historically just or unjust. The
slavery, on the basis of the capitalist mode enforcer of the judgement was, however, the
of production, was therefore as unjust, proletariat (MECW 14, 656).
according to Marx, as the falsification of
commodities (MECW 37, 337 et sqq.). In the 6.5 Since Marx and Engels refused to advo-
Critique of the Gotha Programme, he provo- cate ‘the requirements of truth’ (one could
catively claimed that the wage of the worker, also say: of justice) instead of ‘true’ require-
which in bourgeois society ‘can in no way ments (one could also say: just) and ‘the
be calculated from justice’ is the result of interests of Human Nature, of Man in gen-
the ‘only “just” distribution on the basis of eral’ instead of ‘the interests of the proletariat’
the present-day mode of production’ (MECW (Manifesto, MECW 4, 511), they derived their
24, 84 et sq., trans. modified). Also the communistic demands from the (according
capitalist profited as a ‘necessary functionary to them) empirically perceptible collapse of
of capitalist production [. . .] with every right, the capitalist mode of production, not from
i.e. such right as corresponds to this mode a moral [sittlich] feeling or feeling of justice
of production’ (Randglossen, MECW 24, 535). (MECW 26, 285). While the League of the Just
Marx was not happy that he was obliged to still gave as its goal in Article 3 of its statutes
adopt ‘truth, morality and justice’ in the of 1838 the ‘realisation of the principles
preamble of the Rules of the International which are contained in the rights of man
Workingmen’s Association (MECW 20, 14; 23, and the citizen’ (qtd in Förder, 93), Article
4), ‘but these are placed in such a way that 1 of the 1847 Rules of the Communist League
they can do no harm’ (MECW 42, 11). (on which Marx and Engels worked) stated
that its goal was ‘the overthrow of the
6.4. The radical rejection of the derivation bourgeoisie, the rule of the proletariat, the
of political-revolutionary demands from an abolition of the old bourgeois society which
abstract concept of justice, since ideas had rests on the antagonism of classes, and the
always disgraced themselves as long as they foundation of a new society without classes
were differentiated from interests (HF, and without private property’ (MECW 6,
MECW 4, 85), meant for Marx and Engels 633). This ‘new society’ was defined in the
in no way a lack of criticism in relation to Manifesto as an ‘association, in which the
the given mode of production together with free development of each is the condition
its law and a justice appropriate to it. Since for the free development of all’ (MECW 6,
they understood bourgeois society as an 506).
historical process (i.e. as having become, as With this characterisation, which was also
developing and temporary), they certainly proposed by the late Engels almost fifty
acknowledged no natural justice. However, years later as the foundational idea of the
they did acknowledge, next to a juridical coming socialist epoch (MECW 50, 256), both
justice (what is fair in law) and a social justice a standard for judgement, but also for
(social fairness), also an historical justice. By condemnation of behaviour and relations,
this, they understood the degree of agree- is provided. Something similar is the case
ment of the behaviours and relations of for the demand, already proposed by the
humans with the objective requirements of young Marx in the form of a categorical
social, progressive development. In this imperative, to throw down all relations in
sense, they spoke of ‘historical justification’ which man is an enslaved being (MECW 3,
(AD, MECW 25, 269), of a ‘legitimate 182); and also for the necessary transition of
tendency’ (MECW 20, 188), of an ‘historical the previously merely partial emancipation
inevitability’, that is, the ‘historical legiti- of man to a universal, really human
macy’ of determinant social conditions emancipation (MECW 3, 151, 155, 184); and
(MECW 26, 597 et sqq.), occasionally also also for the principle of socialism or commu-
directly of ‘historically justified’ relations of nism formulated by the late Marx following
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 351

HKWM – Justice • 351

Saint-Simon (c.f. Ramm, 89) of ‘from each not only the use but even the threat of atomic
according to their ability, to each according bombs is unlawful (and thus also unjust),
to their work’ or ‘from each according to NATO did not feel obliged to pacify its
their ability, to each according to their needs’ concepts of war and to refrain from its war-
(Gotha, MECW 24, 85 et sqq.). Even Marx’s practices. Apart from gnoseological, axio-
insight that no society as a totality, no nation logical, logical or sociological treatments and
and not even all contemporaneous societies remarks of a meta-theoretical type about
taken together are ‘owners of the globe’, conceptions of justice of others, three types
but only its ‘usufructuaries’ who have ‘to of theories of modern justice can be dis-
leave their property improved upon to the tinguished. They are, to be precise, agnostic
following generations’ (MECW 37, 762; trans. and – following a classification of Max Weber
modified) contains criteria, if not verbatim (Rechtssoziologie, 243) – material and formal
then certainly in its conceptual content, for theories.
the assessment of the ecological politics of
the state as either just or unjust. 7.1. According to the agnostics, the fact that
In summary: Marx and Engels operated something is just can be just as little proved
with both an ideology-critique concept of scientifically as the beauty of a gothic
justice and also a normative concept of cathedral or a symphony of Beethoven
justice. They preferred the reflexive com- (Ehrlich 1913/89, 163). To the scientist, justice
pared with the constitutive properties of is suspect as a rather political or religious
justice, the reflection of historical events concept (Dürrenmatt 1969, 18). Justice is
in ideas of justice compared with their incompatible with objectivity (Weber, WL,
repercussions on the course of history. 505, 600). It could be an object of confessions
Fixated above all on the (in their opinion) of faith [von Bekenntnissen], but not of
imminent revolution in which capitalist knowledges [von Erkenntnissen]. It is an
relations of production would ‘shed their irrational ideal, based upon arbitrary values
skin’ to reveal socialist relations of product- (Perelman 1967, 82). It is a game with
ion (MECW 37, 762), they undervalued the tautological concepts, burdened by no
reforming potency of demands for justice content, but ready to take up any and every
within the existing social formation. content, that is, it is an empty formula, a
concept smuggled in for disguising stereo-
7. Since the middle of the twentieth century, typed compromises. Or: justice [Gerechtigkeit]
there has been a tendential inflation of has nothing in common with the law [Recht]
literature concerning justice. In times of crisis, except etymology. Viewed scientifically,
the need for an ambiguous vocabulary of the contents of all theories of justice
concealment increases. In the programmes are immediately valid, that is, indifferent.
of all parties, the vocabulary of justice makes The six volumed Handwörterbuch der
an appearance. Nobody holds themselves Rechtswissenschaft (Berlin-Leipzig 1926–37)
and their own concerns to be unjust. It is includes not a single lemma on justice! All
always only others who are unjust. Even postulates of justice which have been pre-
every war is fought by both sides for ‘justice’. viously put forward with claims of absolute-
According to Article 2.3 of the UN Charter ness (e.g. give to each their own; that which
of 1945, the members of the UN have you do not want someone else to do to
committed themselves to settle their disputes you . . .; an eye for an eye . . .; categorical
peacefully, so that ‘peace, security and jus- imperative; to each according to their
tice’ are not endangered. What ‘justice’ is contribution) are tautological (Kelsen 1967,
supposed to mean in this context is not stated 350 et sqq.). The consequence: ‘I do not know
by the UN Charter. The number of the wars what justice is’ (1957, 39).
that were conducted in the second half of
the twentieth century certainly exceeded 7.2. The material theories of justice develop
those of the first half of the century. Even principles and criteria which, according to
though, according to the report of the their own claims, allow an assessment to
International Court of Justice of July 1996, be made regarding content of modes of
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 352

352 • Bastiaan Wielenga, Hermann Klenner and Susanne Lettow

behaviour and relations as just or unjust. example, the family is an ‘order for living
With their help it is supposed to be able to together ’ of the sexes ‘adequate to the
be established whether a valid or planned Creation’, established by God and unable to
law [lex lata or lex ferenda], a war which has be broken by the earthly law giver, in which,
occurred or one which is being planned, the despite the equal rights of man and woman
actual or planed distribution of property in guaranteed by the constitution, the latter
society, gender relations etc. are to be judged safeguards the inner structure of the family,
as just or as unjust. Particularly after the end whose survival and future the man has to
of WWII, as the crimes committed through- ensure, representing the ‘head’ of the family
out Germany’s Third Reich became apparent to the external society (Bundesgerichtshof, cf.
for all to see, the moral and legal philoso- Maihofer, 572 et sqq.).
phical controversies about the theory and
practice of its brutal reign led to an episodic 7.3. Legal-positivist and procedural appro-
justice-renaissance, before legal positivism aches are numbered among the formal
once more triumphed. Gustav Radbruch theories of justice. In the praxis of everyday
had still in 1932 named the sacrificium life, especially that of the jurist, the view
intellectus, ‘only to ask what is legal and which predominates is that justice is, casually
never, if it is also just’ (84), as a professional stated, an automatic consequence of law and
obligation of the judge. In 1946, however, order or, expressed in a highbrow way, the
he stated that ‘turning away from the idea ‘adequate complexity of the legal system’,
of justice’ was responsible for the fact that in which the complexity of a legal system
jurists had become defenceless against the is adequate ‘if and in so far as it is still
criminal laws of the Nazis (196, 209). compatible with consistent decisions in the
Then there emerged theories of justice on system’ (Luhmann 1981, 388, 390).
Catholic (Auer, Messner, Utz) and evangel- Procedural theories have dominated for
ical (Brunner, Wolf, Weinkauff) foundations quite some time in the more detached
as well as value and existential philosophical thought practices. Currently, more than 30
arguments (Coing, Heydte, Fechner) of quite different versions have been represented in
different content, in which assertions were monographs (cf. Tschentscher 2000, 143
rather rarely covered by proofs; ‘intuitive et sqq.). Here it is a case of theories that
vision’, ‘belief in the triune God’ and a ‘meta- are indifferent to content, which restrict
physical order of being’ replaced rational themselves to a justice of procedure, in
argumentation (cf. Maihofer 1966, 39, 195, distinction to the material theories which
213). With the claim that justice could not strive for a justice of the outcome.
be learnt but only experienced, not thought, Thus, for example, John Rawls caused a
but only observed, irrationalities were stir with the following thought-experiment:
indulged and along with it an ideology a rational individual equipped with a healthy
antithetical to democracy – because it is not self-esteem, chosen at random like in a
that the people want a law which makes lottery, should imagine itself to be in an orig-
it just. inary situation with the task of developing
Moreover, the overdue conflicts were for principles of justice. There, hidden under a
the most part carried out at a level of ‘veil of ignorance’, the individual should
abstraction that allowed an approach to decide ‘what sort of society it would consider
reality, above all to its contradictions, to be to be just if it had to live in it’, in ignorance,
neglected. The return to a concept of justice of course, about what sex, age, nationality,
valid for one and all times and all peoples social standing, work and income it would
was also partly used to avoid an analysis of have in the just society which they conceived.
the actual conditions of emergence and Rawls then claimed that this individual
efficacy of the legal and illegal state terrorism would establish two fundamental principles
from 1933 to 1945. Outdated hierarchies were with the status of Kant’s categorical
also declared to be inviolable with the argu- imperative, namely: ‘Everyone has the same
ment that they belonged to the ‘cornerstones right to the most substantial total system of
of Christian European culture’. Thus, for equal fundamental freedoms which is
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 353

HKWM – Justice • 353

possible for everyone’, and: ‘Social and under the structural conditions of a present
economic inequalities must be such that: (a) distribution of power/powerlessness which,
they must [. . .] bring the least favoured the for its part, is certainly not the result of a
greatest possible advantage, and (b) they discourse concerning justice. Consequently,
must be connected with offices and positions the discourse concerning justice is burdened
which are open to all in accordance with fair exclusively on those who have an interest
equality of chances’ (1999, 325). In this in the transformation of society, while those
construct, in which freedom is granted who feel at ease in and affirmed by the
priority before equality and neither private society as it is have no obligation to justify
property nor monogamy are ‘subject of themselves.
political bargaining’, values are radically de-
linked from interests. Nevertheless, the 8. Even if Marx and Engels have left behind
categories of the welfare state, even if no theory of justice, their influences on the
subordinated to those of the state founded ideas of justice of the thinkers who have
upon the rule of law, become discussable followed in their footsteps (and even of their
and the justice-content of contemporary opponents) are of a many and diverse nature.
society is able to be analysed, at least in However, up until now, they have only led
an academic context. Precisely for this to an independent, genuinely Marxist theory
reason, Rawls has already been exposed to of justice in the case of Ernst Bloch.
a growing critique by neoliberals, according In so far as Kautsky, Lenin, Luxemburg,
to whom the compensation by the state Liebknecht, Renner, Bukharin, Korsch,
for natural inequalities transforms the Benjamin, Pashukanis and Stuchka have
state into a ‘machinery for egalitarian spoken about justice at all, they have
redistribution’ (cf. Kersting 2000, 161, 299, concentrated – just as did Marx and Engels
392). – on the characteristic of ideas of justice to
According to Jürgen Habermas’s proce- reflect material interests and relations at the
dural theory of justice, all political power same time as they obscure them (Klenner
should be derived from the communicative 1998, 70 et sqq.). In the lands of ‘really
power of citizens, which is why a legal existing socialism’, one restricted oneself in
system is just to the extent it uniformly the main to an identification of socialist law
ensures the equally originary autonomy of with justice or to an unreflective rendition,
its citizens. Fundamental principles and for the most part one-sidedly, of selected
norms which embody interests that can be comments by Marx and Engels on justice
generalised must be sought in a ‘commu- (exceptions include, for example, Szabó 1973,
nicative arrangement’ (1992, 109, 166). Justice 156; Peschka 1974, 129; Klenner 1982, 147).
is thus a consequence of discourses relieved Gramsci, in the context of his conception
of the necessity of activity and unconstrained of civil society, offered sporadic comments
by experience. which began from the janus-faced nature of
For the proceduralists, the justice of a law natural law and proposed to introduce
or of a social relation should, therefore, not ‘“right” as it is understood by the people’
be dependent upon whether their content is (Q 27, § 2), that is, their representations of
just, but whether they were produced in a justice, into the process of the continuous,
just way. Thus the legitimacy of a claim by no means only revolutionary, transfor-
should also not depend upon the truth of mations of society. In this, he understood
that which is claimed. Rather, the truth of the state as a rational ‘teacher’ and the law
that which is claimed depends upon the as a repressive and awarding activity of
legitimacy of the claim. Certainly, just as for civilisation (Q 13, §11).
the truth, the way and not merely the result For Brecht, who, as both poet and thinker,
also belongs to justice. Nevertheless, all often and suddenly expressed his views on
theories of justice which limit themselves to problems of law and justice (cf. Klenner
the realm of procedure conceal the fact that 1984, 210 et sqq.), justice was a ‘question of
a future, more just, distribution of power production’ (GA 18, 152). And a question of
can only be discussed and decided upon struggle: ‘Whoever does not insist upon their
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 354

354 • Bastiaan Wielenga, Hermann Klenner and Susanne Lettow

just demands deals indecently [unsittlich]’ into hypocrisy (226). As a ‘necessary evil’,
(GA 14, 179). As a materialist, he added justice from below would also function as a
cunningly that one could only struggle for ‘revolutionary tribunal’, ‘enduring only so
justice when one struggled for one’s own long as is possible’, because: ‘No democracy
interests; there is only a ‘justice for whom’ without socialism, no socialism without
(GA 21, 399). For the oppressed, it was not democracy, that is the formula of an
that oppression should cease and then there interaction which decides upon the future’
would be justice, but that there should be (231 et sqq.).
justice, and then oppression would cease;
the oppressed are not selfless, just people 9. In modernity, ‘justice’ has also served a
(GA 18, 53, 153). Opposed to the universalism series of declarations concerning human
of the justice-form of ideas, Brecht stated rights and other laws as a word of intention
regarding the famous verse from the Bible, without resonance on the legal terrain. The
‘You should love your neighbour as you love opening sentence of the Universal Declaration
yourself’ (Lev 19, 18; Mt 22, 39), that ‘If the of Human Rights of the UNO of 1948 (pre-
workers did that they will never abolish a sented as a ‘common standard of achieve-
situation in which one can only love his ment’, that is, not bound to the laws of any
neighbour when one does not love one’s particular people) declares that the recog-
self’ (GA 18, 152). Brecht extended Kant’s nition of human rights is ‘the foundation of
categorical imperative (WA 7, 51) in the freedom, justice and peace in the world’.
sentence: ‘Create a situation in which your This claim is repeated literally in the double
action can be the maxim for the action of catalogue of human rights of December 1966,
everyone’ (GA 22, 279; a very similar idea International Covenant on Economic, Social and
appears in Gramsci, Q 11, § 58). Brecht was Cultural Rights and the International Covenant
among the strongest critics of a substitution on Civil and Political Rights. Indeed, it appears
of values for interests which was appearing in the opening sentences of both documents
now and again even among those on the that have in the meantime become binding
Left. in international law for the great majority
Ernst Bloch’s influential conception of of the world’s states. It is the same in the
natural law is at the same time a conception Preamble of the European Convention for the
of justice. In agreement with Engels, who Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental
described natural law as a ‘an image of the Freedoms of 1950 and the Fundamental Laws
conservative or revolutionary tendencies of of the Federal Republic of Germany (Grundgesetz
his [Dühring’s] day’ (AD, MECW 25, 89), für die Bundesrepublik Deutschland) of 1949
but also with Max Weber, who named it a (Art. 1.2). Judges in Germany have to swear
form of legitimacy of forces which had been that they serve only truth and justice (Richter-
created in revolution but which had also gesetz of 1972, § 38). The German Sozial-
historically become authoritarian (RS, 317 gesetzbuch of 1975 gives as its goal that it
et sqq.), Bloch opposed to ‘justice from on should contribute to ‘social justice’ (I, §1).
high’ (1961, 50 et sqq.) a ‘justice, but from The more the vocabulary of justice is used
below’ (227 et sqq.). The ‘eye of the laws’ in theoretical, programmatic and legal texts
(206) on the face of the ruling class would in a way which is empty of content, the
not be endangered by the Sunday ideal of greater is the danger that justice only serves
a justice from on high, but by the ‘radical, injustice as window dressing (Bloch 11),
subjective natural law and its demand: from instead of mobilising against this injustice.
each according to their abilities, to each Whenever ‘justice’ is spoken of, one must
according to their needs’, to which corres- always be mindful of whose interests are
ponded ‘the radical objective natural law: appealed to. Using the vocabulary of justice,
solidarity’ (269; cf. 252). This natural law the media of the powerful are advertising
from below is not innate; for Marxism ‘the for a penetration of the forms of capital into
humanum’ was valid ‘as an historical goal, the global society by suggesting to those
not as an apriori principle of deduction’ without power the possibility of the general-
(219). The more suprahistorically natural law isation of interests that cannot be generalised.
was traded, the more quickly it degenerated Should one, therefore, renounce completely
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 355

HKWM – Justice • 355

the code of justice/injustice, since it is con- nach der gerechten Gesellschaft’, in K.V. Bonin
stantly misused as a façade of legitimation? (ed.), 1997, Deutscher Evangelischer Kirchentag 1997,
Who ever gives up the uncovering of the 286–96, Gütersloh; H. KLENNER, 1998, Recht und
Gerechtigkeit, Marxistische Lesehefte 1, Berlin; H.
power/powerlessness structure of society, K LENNER 1999, ‘Aufklärungshistorisches zur
whose mode of being is causal for the sozialen Gerechtigkeit’, in Z, 10. Jg., Nr. 40, 24–33;
injustice of the powerful against the H. KLENNER, 2000, ‘Religion and Right in Marx’,
powerless, would only encourage those who in M. Friedman (ed.), 2000, Rights and Reason,
do not shrink from draping a coat of Boston, 263–70; W. KOWALSKI, 1962, Vorgeschichte
moralistic-juridical non-conditionality and und Entstehung des Bundes der Gerechten, Berlin/
GDR; A. LAUBE and H. SEIFFERT (eds.), 1978, Flug-
non-evasion around the money-making schriften der Bauernkriegszeit, 2nd edition, Berlin/
policies of the rich and the monopoly of GDR; N. LUHMANN, 1981, ‘Gerechtigkeit in den
violence of the ruling class. Rechtssystemen der modernen Gesellschaft’, in
In June of 1953 Brecht wrote of justice as N. LUHMANN, 1981, Ausdifferenzierung des Rechts,
the ‘bread of the people’ which, to be sure, 374–418; Frankfurt/M; A. MAIHOFER, 1992, ‘Thesen
must be baked by the people themselves zur Gerechtigkeit’, in A. MAIHOFER, 1992, Das Recht
bei Marx, 65–89, Baden-Baden; W. MAIHOFER (ed.),
(GA 15, 269). 1966, Naturrecht oder Rechtspositivismus, Bad
Homburg; J. M ESSNER , 1984, Das Naturrecht,
BIBLIOGRAPHY: W. BENJAMIN, 1978 [1921], ‘Critique Berlin/W; H. MONZ, 1995, Gerechtigkeit bei Marx
of Violence’, in Reflections, 277–300, New York; E. und in der hebräischen Bibel, Baden-Baden; Th. MORE
BLOCH, 1961, Naturrecht und menschliche Würde, 1974 [1516], Utopia, Harmondsworth; E. PASHUKANIS,
Frankfurt/M; B. BRECHT, 1988–2003, Große kom- 1991 [1924], Allgemeine Rechtslehre und Marxismus,
mentierte Berliner und Frankfurter Ausgabe (GA), Freiburg-Berlin; C. P ERELMAN , 1967, Über die
Berlin-Weimar-Frankfurt/M; E. BRUNNER, 1943, Gerechtigkeit, München; V. P E S C H K A , 1974,
Gerechtigkeit, Zürich; A.E. BUCHANAN, 1982, Marx Grundprobleme der modernen Rechtsphilosophie,
and Justice, London; G. BÜCHNER, 1968, Werke und Budapest; P.J. PROUDHON, 1858, De la justice, Paris;
Briefe, Leipzig; H. C OING , 1993, Grundzüge der G. R ADBRUCH , 1999 (3rd edition 1932), Rechts-
Rechtsphilosophie, Berlin; F. D ÜRRENMATT , 1969, philosophie, Heidelberg; G. RADBRUCH, ‘Entwurf
Monstervortrag über Gerechtigkeit und Recht, Zürich; eines Nachworts’ (1946), in ibid., 193–208;
E. EHRLICH, 1989 [1913], Grundlegung der Soziologie G. RADBRUCH, ‘Fünf Minuten Rechtsphilosophie’
des Rechts, Berlin/W; H. FÖRDER, M. HUNDT (eds.), (1946), in ibid., 209–10; T. RAMM (ed.), 1956, Der
1983, Der Bund der Kommunisten. Dokumente und Frühsozialismus. Quellentexte, Stuttgart; J. RAWLS,
Materialien, Vol. 1, Berlin/GDR; W. GODWIN, 1976 1999 [1971], A Theory of Justice, Cambridge/Mass.;
[1793], An Enquiry Concerning Political Justice, J.-J. R OUSSEAU , 1997 [1755], Diskurs über die
Harmondsworth; A. GRAMSCI, 1975, Quaderni del Ungleichheit/Discours sur l’inégalité, ed. H. Meier,
carcere (Q), Turin; S. HAACKE, 1994, Zuteilen und Paderborn; J. ROUX, 1985 [1793], Freiheit wird die
Vergelten. Figuren der Gerechtigkeit bei Aristoteles, Welt erobern, Leipzig; H. SCHRÖDER, 1979, Die Frau
Wien; J. HABERMAS, 1992, ‘Gerechtigkeitskonzepte’, ist frei geboren. Texte, München; E.-I. SZABÓ, 1973,
in J. HABERMAS, 1992, Faktizität und Geltung, 61–108, Les fondements de la théorie du droit, Budapest;
Frankfurt/M; G.W.F. HEGEL, 1952, Philosophy of E.-I. S Z A B Ó , 1982, Karl Marx und das Recht,
Right (PR), tr. T. M. Knox, Oxford; G.W.F. HEGEL, Berlin/GDR; A. TSCHENTSCHER, 2000, Prozedurale
1971, Werke in zwanzig Bänden (W), Frankfurt/M; Theorien der Gerechtigkeit, Baden-Baden; M. WEBER,
G.W.F. HEGEL, 1977, Phenomenology of Spirit (PS), 1967, Rechtssoziologie, Neuwied; M. WEBER, 1985
tr. A.V. Miller, Oxford; J. HÖPPNER and W. SEIDEL- [1922], Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Wissenschaftslehre
HÖPPNER, 1975, Von Babeuf bis Blanqui. Texte, Leipzig; (WL), Tübingen; W. WEITLING, 1976 [1845], Das
I. KANT, 1968, Werkausgabe (WA), ed. W. Weischedel, Evangelium des armen Sünders, Leipzig; W. WEITLING,
Frankfurt/M; H. K ELSEN , 1957 [1953], What Is 1929 [1843], Gerechtigkeit, Kiel; E. WOLF, 1984,
Justice?, Berkeley; H. KELSEN, 1967 [1934], Pure ‘Naturrecht’, in Historisches Wörterbuch der Philo-
Theory of Law, Berkeley; H. KELSEN, 1985, Die Illusion sophie 6, 560–623; M. WOLLSTONECRAFT, 1994, A
der Gerechtigkeit, Wien; W. KERSTING, 2000, Theorien Vindication of the Rights of Women, A Vindication of
der sozialen Gerechtigkeit, Stuttgart; H. KLENNER, the Rights of Men, Oxford.
1982, ‘Gerechtigkeit – eine rechtsphilosophische
Kategorie?’, in H. KLENNER, 1982, Marxismus und
Menschenrechte, 147–58, Berlin/GDR; H. KLENNER, Hermann Klenner
1984, ‘Marx/Engels-Anthologie zur Natur des
Rechts’, in H. KLENNER, 1984, Vom Recht der Natur Translated by Peter Thomas
zur Natur des Rechts, Berlin/GDR, 79–138; H.
KLENNER, 1991, ‘Der rechtsphilosophische Denk- Anerkennung, Armut/Reichtum, Bürgerrechte,
Einsatz von Marx’, in H. KLENNER, 1991, Deutsche Emanzipation, Ethik, falsches Bewusstsein,
Rechtsphilosophie im 19. Jahrhundert. Essays, 155–75, feministische Rechtskritik, Freiheit, Gegenmacht,
Berlin; H. KLENNER, 1997, ‘Karl Marx und die Frage gerechter Lohn, gerechter Krieg, Geschlechtervertrag,
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 356

356 • Bastiaan Wielenga, Hermann Klenner and Susanne Lettow

Gesellschaftsvertrag, Gewissen, Gleichheit, Interesse, Ronald Dworkin and John Rawls. Rawls
Juristen-Sozialismus, juristische Weltanschauung, spoke out, with Keynes, for the ‘priority of
Klassenjustiz, Konsens, Legalität, Menschenrechte, justice over and above the ability to perform
Moral, moralische Ökonomie, Naturrecht, Normen, and greater sum total of profit’ (1999, 324).
Phrase, Recht, Rechtsstaat, Sozialstaat, Toleranz, While the neoliberal ‘new interpretation
Tyrannei, Universalismus, Utopie, Werte. of the social question’, as Birgit Mahnkopf
civil rights, class justice, conscience, consensus,
(2000) demonstrated, became established in
counterpower, emancipation, empty phrase, equality,
the political objectives of social democracy
ethics, fair wages, false consciousness, feminist legal
thanks to the formula of ‘justice through
critique, freedom, gender contract, human rights,
inequality’, its critique has remained for the
interest, juridical socialism, juridical Weltanschauung,
most part trapped in a helpless rhetoric of
just war, law, legality, morality, moral economy, natural
‘values’. The articulation of justice as value
law, norms, poverty/wealth, Rechtsstaat, recognition,
has proved to be itself a method, even when
social contract, tolerance, tyranny, universalism, utopia,
it remains linked to ‘equality’, by means of
values, welfare state.
which the renunciation of emancipatory
politics becomes hegemonic or at least
capable of exercising hegemony. Anthony
III. After the collapse of administrative Giddens formulated this affirmatively: ‘In
socialism and the triumph march of neo- the absence of a model of liberation the self-
liberalism, there was a sudden increase of description of “left-wing” actually becomes
publications on the problem of justice in in the first instance a question of values’
which neoliberal and post-Keynesian (2000, 45 et sqq.). Herlinde Pauer-Studer
positions came into conflict. – The neoliberal (2000) answered the social-philosophical
positions worked on a conceptual decoupling ‘anti-egalitarianism’ with the construction
of justice and equality. Justice was articulated of a universe of values in which equality as
as ‘suum cuique [to each their due]’, and an ‘extrinsic, instrumental value’ arbitrated
the classical conception of ‘proportional over ‘freedom’ as extrinsic value ‘in itself’,
justice’ was combined with one of the and the ‘intrinsic value’ of universal respect
leading concepts of neoliberalism: ‘Every was assigned an admittedly subordinate but
person should is entitled to the rights, secure place. While the dispute about justice
respect, consideration and participation upon was centred on the question of whether
which they are able to make a claim on the ‘equality’ was an intrinsic or merely derived
basis of who they are and what they have value (Pauer-Studer 2000; Frankfurt 2000;
achieved’ (Frankfurt 2000, 42). A ‘minimal Krebs 2000), the social problematic dis-
welfare state’ was pleaded for (Kersting), appeared over the horizon.
which was oriented to the so-called The so-called abilities-approach of
sufficiency-principle: ‘To own less is in the Amartya Sen and Martha Nussbaum,
end compatible with owning much, and supposedly serving ‘equality and justice’
doing less well than others does not imply (Nussbaum 1999, 63), was oriented, in
that one is doing badly. [. . .] There is no contrast, much more strongly to praxis and
necessary connection between life on the needs. ‘What must finally be in the fore-
bottom rung of society and poverty in the ground’ argued Sen, ‘is the life which we
sense that poverty is a serious and mor- lead: that which we are able or are not able
ally unacceptable obstacle to a good life’ to do, that which we can or cannot be’ (1987,
(Frankfurt 2000, 40). It is the task of the state 36). In opposition to the sufficiency-principle,
to guard the material interest of citizen as Sen defined the standard of living necessary
much as is necessary in order to keep them for the development of determinant abilities
‘ready for the market’ (Kersting 2000, 392). from the socially average level of repro-
Similar to the political terrain, here, in the duction. Significantly absent in this concep-
first instance, conceptions oriented to a tion, however, are the practically active, social
Keynesian notion of redistribution are individuals who articulate their interests.
attacked. The opponents of the anti- That it concerns conceptions ‘from above’
egalitarians who are most discussed are which strive to fix what humans are and are
HIMA 13,3_dictionary_333-357 8/23/05 3:36 PM Page 357

HKWM – Justice • 357

not entitled to becomes particularly clear extent justice is linked to demands and
in Nussbaum’s ‘Aristotelian social demo- proposals regarding the dismantlement of
cratism’. In order to concretise Aristotle’s the domination of humans over humans,
concept of the good life, she undertook to therefore moves into the centre of the debate.
present a list of fundamental needs and From a Marxist perspective, it is this question
abilities that should give an answer to the of the critique of domination which cons-
‘question of what seems to belong to a life titutes the centre of discourses concerning
which we accept as a human life’ (199, 190). justice; and it is this horizon in which
Nevertheless this ‘we’ has a dehumanising Derrida’s Benjaminian-Heideggerean claim
reverse-side: the handicapped – and also, in gains its meaning: the ‘absolute and non-
a problematic case, youth fallen on hard anticipatable singularity of that which is-
times – are regarded as examples of a life to-come as justice’ is an ‘irrenunciable
which ‘is so impoverished that it cannot be distinguishing mark of the Marxian legacy’
rightfully called a human life’ (198). The (50).
philosophical classification of human/
inhuman has here taken the place of the BIBLIOGRAPHY: J. DERRIDA, 1994, Specters of Marx, tr.
question concerning the possibilities of the P. Kamuf, London; R. DWORKIN, 1978, Taking Rights
appropriation and shaping of one’s own Seriously, Cambridge/Mass.; H. FRANKFURT, 2000,
conditions of life. ‘Gleichheit und Achtung’, in KREBS 2000, 38–49;
N. F RASER 1997, Justice Interruptus, London;
Nancy Fraser’s contribution to the debate
A. GIDDENS, 2000, The Third Way and Its Critics,
about justice distinguished itself by departing Cambridge; W. KERSTING, 2000, Theorien der sozialen
from the politics of the social movements. Gerechtigkeit, Stuttgart; A. KREBS, 1999, ‘Würde statt
In the ‘post-socialist situation’ she observed Gleichheit. Zu Avishai Margalits “Politik der
a shift in the articulation-forms of the social Würde”’, in DZPh, 47. Jg., H. 2, 291–311; A. KREBS,
movements: ‘Cultural domination supplants 2000, ‘Einleitung: Die neue Egalitarismuskritik im
Überblick’, in A. KREBS (ed.), 2000, Gleichheit oder
exploitation as the fundamental injustice.
Gerechtigkeit, 7–37, Frankfurt/M; B. MAHNKOPF,
And cultural recognition displaces socio- 2000, ‘Die Formel 1 der neuen Sozialdemokratie:
economic redistribution as the remedy for Gerechtigkeit durch Ungleichheit’, in Prokla 121,
injustice and the goal of political struggle’ 31. Jg., 489–525; M. NUSSBAUM, 1999, Gerechtigkeit
(1997, 11). For Fraser, ‘justice today requires oder Das gute Leben, Frankfurt/M; H. PAUER-STUDER,
both redistribution and recognition’ (12). She 2000, Autonom leben, Frankfurt/M; J. RAWLS, 1999
[1971], A Theory of Justice, Cambridge/Mass;
developed a perspective against paternalistic
A. SEN, 1987, The Standard of Living, Cambridge.
social policy and exclusivist identity politics
which combined ‘the socioeconomic politics
of socialist feminism with the cultural politics Susanne Lettow
of deconstructive feminism’ (29). The socialist
Translated by Peter Thomas
component aimed at a ‘transformative
redistribution’ which included a ‘deep res-
Anerkennung, Distribution, Feminismus, Gleichheit,
tructuring of the relations of production’
Keynesianismus, Leistung, Neoliberalismus,
(27). The deconstructive component was an
Sozialdemokratie, Sozialfürsorge, Sozialpolitik,
‘opponent of the sort of sedimentation or
Sozialstaat.
congealing of gender difference that occurs
in an unjustly gendered political economy’ achievement, distribution, equality, feminism,
(30). With the formula ‘recognition and Keynesianism, neoliberalism, recognition, social
redistribution’ Fraser joined together the democracy, social politics, social welfare, welfare state.
cultural and socio-economic dimensions of
socialist politics in a purely additive way
and detached from any real policies.
Nevertheless, it became clear in her study
that justice throws up questions of social
transformation. Not whether the concept of
justice can and should be connected with
the concept of equality, but, rather, to what

Вам также может понравиться