Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 8

Marine Policy 117 (2020) 103945

Contents lists available at ScienceDirect

Marine Policy
journal homepage: http://www.elsevier.com/locate/marpol

Welfare economics and wicked problems in coastal and marine governance


Rolf A. Groeneveld
Wageningen University, Environmental Economics and Natural Resources Group, Hollandseweg 1, 6706 KN, Wageningen, the Netherlands

A B S T R A C T

Coastal and marine governance has been characterised as a ‘wicked’ problem due to difficulties in definition, uncertainty, and conflicting perspectives and values.
Social Cost-Benefit Analysis (SCBA), which is an application of welfare economics, ’tames’ such problems by assuming away many of these complexities. This article
reviews the simplifying assumptions underlying SCBA in four major areas. First, welfare-economics and SCBA assume a utilitarian, consequentialist frame and a clear
problem delineation, whereas wicked problems are difficult to define and delineate. Second, welfare economics can deal with risk and uncertainty as long as all
policy alternatives, states of nature, and success criteria are known, whereas for wicked problems it is not known with certainty which alternatives are to be evaluated
and by which criteria, and which states of nature are possible. Third, welfare economics can deal with a variety of perceptions as long as the legitimacy of each
perception is uncontested, whereas in wicked problems some stakeholders’ or experts’ views are contested by others. Fourth, welfare economics can deal with a
variety of preferences and hence conflicting interests, as long as all values are individual and substitutable, whereas in wicked problems some values cannot be
substituted as they represent ‘sacred’ values such as religion and identity. Despite its limitations, however, the explicit definition of the assumptions behind SCBA
make it a helpful benchmark to determine what makes a given problem in coastal and marine governance wicked.

1. Introduction degree of term inflation, and some authors have warned that the term is
being applied too liberally [20–22]. In contrast, the basis of SCBA, i.e.
The difficulty of marine governance goes beyond mere complexity welfare economics, is characterised by a set of clear and explicit as­
[1]. Seas are three-dimensional systems that are difficult to monitor and sumptions that enable practitioners to express the desirability of policy
poorly understood; rights of access and property are contested; coastal options in quantitative, i.e. monetary terms.
and marine areas are strongly interconnected biophysically and socially; The wicked problems concept and SCBA therefore represent two
and a multitude of interests are involved [1,2]. The decision who gets alternative ways to frame normative dilemmas in coastal and marine
access to marine resources, for which activities, where, and when, in­ governance. The first frame, wicked problems, acknowledges the many
volves considerations of a biophysical, social, economic, and moral na­ complexities and contradictions faced by policy makers, but in preser­
ture that are difficult to disentangle. ving that complexity it struggles to provide clear policy recommenda­
Social Cost-Benefit Analysis (SCBA) is commonly used to appraise tions; it also lacks a clear and universally accepted definition. The
marine policies [3–6]. Examples of SCBA in coastal and marine gover­ second frame, SCBA, provides seemingly clear policy recommendations
nance include adaptation to climate change (see e.g. Refs. [7–9]; water based on a well-defined normative model, but only at the expense of
quality standards [10]; deep sea mining [11]; marine protected areas ‘taming’ the wicked problem, i.e. assuming away many aspects of the
[12,13]; and offshore wind energy (see e.g. Ref. [14]. problem relevant to policy makers.
However, SCBA may also oversimplify the problems at hand. Jentoft Therefore, contrasting the assumptions made in welfare economics
and Chuenpagdee [1] argues that marine governance is a ‘wicked’ with the characteristics of wicked problems will be useful for both policy
problem (cf [15]. Unlike ‘tame’ problems, which can be technically scientists and economists. There is a need in policy science for a clearer
complex but are unambiguously defined and solved, wicked problems diagnosis of what makes a given problem wicked. Peters [21] argues
lack a clear definition, they are highly uncertain, and there is no that the term “wicked problems” has been applied to problems that, in
consensus on which solution is preferred. The ‘wicked’ characteristics of the strictest sense of the term, should not be considered wicked. Alford
many problems addressed by the social sciences are typically ignored by and Head [20] suggest a typology of wicked problems that acknowl­
welfare-economic policy appraisal tools such as SCBA. edges that some problems are more wicked than others, and in different
What exactly constitutes a wicked problem, however, is itself subject respects. Neither, however, have considered welfare economics as a
to confusion. Various definitions of wicked problems exist (see e.g. frame of reference to diagnose the wickedness of a given problem.
Ref. [16–19]. This definitional vagueness has led to a considerable For economists, studying wicked problems can highlight the most

E-mail address: rolf.groeneveld@wur.nl.

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.marpol.2020.103945
Received 27 May 2019; Received in revised form 7 March 2020; Accepted 12 March 2020
Available online 20 March 2020
0308-597X/© 2020 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
R.A. Groeneveld Marine Policy 117 (2020) 103945

important limitations in welfare economics and by extension SCBA, and Compared to private CBA carrying out an SCBA raises two major
suggest promising avenues for future research on the embedding of difficulties. The first difficulty is the lack of a market price for many
economic analysis in public decision-making procedures. There is an relevant effects. Whereas private CBA takes market prices for granted,
extensive literature on the applicability of SCBA and monetary valuation SCBA also takes into account effects for which no markets exist, such as
to coastal and marine governance [5,6,23–25]. So far, however, this environmental pollution, degradation of biodiversity, or restoration of
literature has focused on the availability of scientific data and models, ecosystems [4]. Monetising such issues as health, safety, and aesthetic
and it has hardly discussed the philosophical foundations of quality also raises ethical objections [30]. Proponents of welfare eco­
welfare-economic analysis itself. An exception is Oinonen et al. [24], nomics argue that when really pressed for a decision, people do make
who acknowledge that in addition to the instrumental and anthropo­ choices that they initially deem unpalatable: they choose cheaper but
centric values included in SCBA there are more qualitative consider­ riskier commuting options, or do not donate all their wealth to charity.
ations that are also important, but the authors do not explain or explore Once we accept this assumption of substitutability, we can estimate
what those considerations might be. Torres and Hanley [25] highlight in people’s Compensating Variation (CV), i.e. the monetary transaction
their discussion the need for more interdisciplinary approaches to that makes the individual as well off as without the change, or their
address concerns of rights, fairness, and social and environmental im­ Equivalent Variation (EV), i.e. the monetary transaction that makes the
pacts that cannot be monetised as these concerns are difficult to include individual as well off as they would have been with it.
in an SCBA. None of these sources discuss or mention the wicked Second, whereas a private company only has its own interest to
problems concept, and to the best of my knowledge Batie [26] is the only worry about, SCBA aggregates the effects over multiple individuals.
study discussing in detail the challenge posed by wicked problems to Interpersonal comparison of CV or EV is hampered by income differ­
economics, albeit in general terms. ences: when two people with different income levels have the same CV
The objective of this paper is to trace the limitations and simplifying for an environmental effect, the effect is probably more important in
assumptions of welfare economics, and its application in SCBA, vis-� a-vis utility terms to the poorer person than to the richer person [31]. SCBA
the characteristics of wicked problems, with a focus on coastal and can potentially weight income groups differently based on (1) the in­
marine resources. In doing so the paper aims to shed light on the dividual’s marginal utility of consumption, i.e. richer individuals’
following questions: (1) which are the assumptions commonly made in higher willingness to pay for a change with the same utilitarian value;
welfare economics that ‘tame’ the problem at hand? and (2) how can and (2) the marginal moral value of utility, i.e. the marginal increase in
welfare economics serve as a benchmark to identify the ‘wicked’ char­ society’s welfare due to an increase in the individual’s welfare [31].
acteristics of problems in marine governance? Equity weights are not commonly used, however, because most SCBAs
The paper is organised as follows. Section 2 discusses SCBA and its follow the Kaldor-Hicks potential compensation principle [32,33] that a
foundation in welfare economics, the literature on wicked problems, and policy is considered welfare-improving if its winners can compensate the
their position in the public decision-making process. Section 3 discusses losers and still be better off.
four major characteristics of wicked problems: problem definition, risk Intergenerational equity gives rise to similar contests between moral
and uncertainty, conflicting beliefs, and conflicting values; and the as­ premises. Traditionally SCBA discounts future effects to take into ac­
sumptions made in welfare economics to ‘tame’ the problem. Section 4 count future economic growth as well as genuine impatience. For
discusses the main findings and suggestions for further research. problems with long time horizons (affecting future generations) and
high uncertainty, the discount rate is debated (see e.g. Refs. [34,35].
2. Welfare-economic analysis and wicked problems in the
marine policy cycle 2.2. Role of Social Cost-Benefit Analysis in public decision-making

2.1. Theoretical basis of Social Cost-Benefit Analysis Formally SCBA is carried out in the appraisal phase of the policy
cycle, i.e. when objectives have been defined and alternative policies to
SCBA is an application of welfare economics, which in turn is an achieve the objectives need to be selected [36–38] Within the appraisal
application of utilitarian ethics. The founder of utilitarianism, Jeremy phase, however, one can distinguish several sub-phases, from a general
Bentham, argued that actions be judged by their utility, i.e. the extent to exploration of the solution space to the selection of specific policy in­
which they increase pleasure or reduce pain [27]. Welfare economics terventions. In each of these sub-phases SCBA is used, albeit at different
interprets utility as a cardinal representation of an individual preference levels of detail from “rough” back-of-the-envelope SCBAs to shorten a
ordering rather than a variable of hedonic experience, but two relevant long-list of options, to detailed analyses to appraise a specific policy
characteristics of utilitarianism remain. First, utilitarianism is conse­ proposal [36–39].
quentialist: it judges the morality of an action by its consequences rather In coastal and marine governance application of SCBA is driven by
than the act itself or the intentions behind it. Second, utilitarianism is legal requirements as well as increasing claims on marine areas. Policies
welfarist, i.e. it follows “the principle that the goodness of a state of in the United States where a CBA was obliged under Executive Order
affairs depends ultimately on the set of individual utilities in that state, 12866 [40] included, among others, various measures taken within
and […] can be seen as an increasing function of that set” [28]:464). fisheries management plans, environmental regulations for marine
Although utilitarianism is not necessarily anthropocentric [29], a third vessels, and management of marine protected species.1 The European
relevant characteristic of the application of welfare economics in SCBA Union’s Water Framework Directive (WFD) [41] and Marine Strategy
is that it considers only the utility of human beings. Framework Directive (MSFD) [42] require the consideration of costs and
SCBA differs from private cost-benefit analysis, i.e. CBA as under­ benefits in the appraisal of Programmes of Measures to achieve Good
taken by a private firm, in that it is designed to appraise decisions from a Environmental Status. Although SCBA has not been used widely in
public perspective. When deciding about an investment in a project, marine spatial planning, its role is likely to increase [43].
private companies identify and quantify the project’s costs and benefits, The WFD and MSFD have also led to a growing literature on the
and discount future costs and benefits by the market interest rate to take applicability of SCBA, particularly the monetary valuation of ecosystem
into account the opportunity costs of the capital invested. In SCBA, services, in marine governance. Apart from some methodological issues
public decision-making bodies appraise policy decisions by identifying, with valuation methods such as contingent valuation and benefits
quantifying, and monetising all effects on society. Like in a private CBA,
future effects are also discounted, albeit with a social discount rate that
reflects not just the interest rate but also considerations of irreversibility 1
Analysis of datasets available on https://www.reginfo.gov/public/do/
of environmental damage and intergenerational equity [4]. XMLReportList. Code and data available on request.

2
R.A. Groeneveld Marine Policy 117 (2020) 103945

transfers [5,23], the main barrier to the application of ecosystem service climate change (see e.g. Ref. [53,54]. Rather than indicating genuine
valuation and SCBA in marine governance appears to be the lack of data scientific uncertainty, public disputes over scientific expertise corrode
and models to quantify the ecological processes that link human impacts trust in the legitimacy of experts and the knowledge they bring to the
to ecosystem services [5,6,23,24]. decision-making process. In such situations policy-makers face a choice
Ecosystem service valuation is also relevant for the growing promi­ between legitimising maverick views with limited grounding in scien­
nence of Natural Capital Accounting (NCA) in marine governance (see e. tific fact, or disenfranchising the actors that hold those views.
g. Ref. [44–47]. Although NCA is a potentially valuable governance tool, The concept of wicked problems has also attracted criticism. Peters
a fundamental difference from SCBA is that whereas NCA describes the [21] notes that the label “wicked” has been applied rather liberally to a
state of ecological assets as they are and develop over time, SCBA is host of problems. All policy problems to some degree have at least some
applied to specific policy decisions. In other words, whereas SCBA of the characteristics of wicked problems, although some resemble the
mostly resides in the appraisal phase of the policy cycle, the comparative concept more than others. Turnbull and Hoppe [22] notes a false di­
advantage of NCA lies in the other phases, i.e. to identify problems, chotomy between the natural sciences and the social sciences, where
prioritise objectives, and monitor progress [48]. supposedly the former is value-free and the latter is not. Moreover, the
dichotomy between wicked and tame problems suggests a binary un­
2.3. Wicked problems derstanding of wickedness that ignores that some problems can be more
wicked than others. Even problems deemed tame by R&W involve a
The idea that some problems are not merely complicated, but diffi­ scientific practice that is a social process with all the sociocultural and
cult to a degree that makes these problems ‘wicked’, was first introduced political complexities that come with it.
by Rittel and Webber [15] (R&W). The then-dominant technocratic
paradigm approached social planning as a natural-science problem [22], 3. Wicked problems and the assumptions of welfare economics
but R&W urge planners to acknowledge that social problems have
distinct characteristics that make them essentially impossible to solve – 3.1. Classification of wicked problem characteristics
rather, they are ‘resolved’, i.e. solved over and over again. Whereas
natural science addresses ‘tame’ problems, with clear definitions, ob­ Alford and Head [20] classifies wicked problems along two di­
jectives, and success indicators, social science addresses ‘wicked’ prob­ mensions: the problem itself and the actors involved. For the purpose of
lems, i.e. problems that are poorly defined, have unclear objectives, and this article it is helpful to further refine these two characteristics. The
where it is difficult to say whether the problem has been solved. first dimension, i.e. the problem itself, can be wicked for two reasons:
R&W list ten characteristics of wicked problems. First, they lack whether the problem is defined clearly and whether all aspects of the
definitive formulation, not least because problem definition and solution problem are known with certainty. The definition entails the identifi­
are difficult to separate. Wicked problems can only be understood cation of relevant causal factors and the mechanisms by which they lead
through one’s actions to solve them, different problem definitions exist, to undesired outcomes, as well as the problem’s geographical, temporal,
and each problem definition suggests a different solution. Second, and societal scope. Uncertainty entails the fact that some aspects of the
wicked problems have no stopping rule: one cannot say whether the problem, such as causal factors or outcomes of interventions, are un­
problem has been solved, not least because policy makers can always known. With regard to the second dimension, i.e. the actors involved,
find ways to do better. Therefore, policy makers stop addressing a Alford and Head [20] argues that the problem can be wicked because
wicked problem not because they have solved it or have run out of op­ knowledge is fragmented, or because actors have conflicting interests.
tions, but because they run “out of time, money, or patience” [15]:162). This distinction is similar to the distinction between positive and
Third, solutions are not true or false, but can at best be ranked in terms of normative analysis common in economics [55]: people can disagree
‘good’ or ‘bad’. Even such rankings may be impossible because multiple, because they accept or have access to different facts or perspectives, i.e.
possibly conflicting, criteria exist. Fourth, the effects of wicked problems on how things are; or they can disagree on values, i.e. how things should
and their solutions may only become visible in the distant future, pre­ be. Hence this article describes wicked problems by four characteristics:
cluding a timely and ultimate test of success. Fifth, wicked problems (1) they are difficult to define; (2) they entail variables that are uncer­
offer no opportunity for learning by trial-and-error because all solutions tain; (3) actors disagree about facts or perspectives; and (4) actors
have lasting and irreversible repercussions. Sixth, the full set of potential disagree about values. The remainder of this chapter discusses each of
solutions is uncertain as it depends on such factors as ethics, public these four characteristics of wicked problems, their examples in marine
acceptance, and creativity. Seventh, every wicked problem is essentially governance, and the corresponding assumptions in welfare-economic
unique, so that lessons learned from one wicked problem cannot be analysis.
transferred to another wicked problem. Eighth, wicked problems are
generally symptoms of deeper problems. Therefore, ’solutions’ aimed at 3.2. Wicked problems are difficult to define
the immediate wicked problem may fail to address or even exacerbate
the underlying problems; on the other hand, trying to identify and 3.2.1. Definition problems in marine governance
address the ‘fundamental’ problem risks postponing solutions indefi­ Marine systems are complex social-ecological systems where bio­
nitely as the problem lacks a ‘natural’ level where its fundamental causes logical, social, and economic issues are closely linked [1]. Problems such
are found. Ninth, multiple explanations or driving forces exist for the as overfishing or poverty have a multitude of causes, so that it is often
problem, and each suggests a different solution. Tenth, the costs of being difficult to single out one cause of a problem. This complexity has
wrong are high. consequences for the framing of problems, and for the setting of
This list of characteristics has been redefined and expanded (see e.g. geographical and temporal boundaries.
Ref. [1,26,49]. Kreuter et al. [49] adds the dynamic nature of wicked A good example of a framing problem in marine governance is how
problems and their definitions, so that solutions that seem appropriate overfishing is understood in economics and other fields. The common
now become less so in the future; and the absence of shared values, or explanation in economics for depletion of fish stocks is that such stocks
conflicts between values. Jentoft and Chuenpagdee [1] emphasizes the are open-access resources that require well-defined property rights in
fact that different stakeholders hold different perspectives of the prob­ order to be managed sustainably. Longo and Clausen [56], on the other
lem, leading to ambiguity in the problem definition. hand, take a Marxist perspective that highlights intense commodifica­
To these characteristics can be added the emerging problem that tion of bluefin tuna in world markets as the main driver of its decline.
facts or scientific findings are disputed, for example in policy domains Each of these perspectives emphasizes a different factor in the depletion
such as vaccination (see e.g. Ref. [50,51], genetic modification [52], and of bluefin tuna stocks, i.e. lack of property rights and high demand for

3
R.A. Groeneveld Marine Policy 117 (2020) 103945

the resource, and while both perspectives can be right each suggests a 3.3.2. Risk and uncertainty in Social Cost-Benefit Analysis
different solution. Another example is the correlation of fishing with Decision-making under uncertainty in welfare economics can be
poverty in developing countries, which has been interpreted as a sign of formalised as a problem of maximizing expected utility (cf [72]:
stock depletion as well as fishing being an occupation of last resort [57]. ( )
X
With respect to geographical and temporal boundaries, marine eco­ max f ðsÞ � uðfcv ða; sÞjv 2 VgÞ (1)
systems are often strongly connected to other ecosystems or regions [2], a2A
s2S
making the delineation of a marine problem rather arbitrary. It can also
The utility function, u, ranks outcomes of policies in terms of their
take a long time before effects of an intervention manifest themselves
desirability, which is assumed to be a cardinal variable and depends on
[2]. This long time lag between intervention and effect creates un­
the value, cv , of a set of variables, V, deemed important by the decision
certainties even in well-monitored systems.
maker. In fisheries policy, V could include the economic performance of
the commercial fleet, the number of jobs in the fishery, and the health of
3.2.2. Problem definition in Social Cost-Benefit Analysis
the fish stock, whereas u determines how different combinations of
SCBA frames problems in at least two ways. First, its consequen­
economic performance, employment, and stock health are ranked. The
tialism frames the problem as one of maximizing the expected outcome
value of each variable depends on the action taken by the policy-maker
of policy, rather than finding the ‘root cause’ of a problem. This could
(a 2 A) and the state of nature (s 2 S), where the latter depends on a
override considerations of justice, which is a common objection to
stochastic process.
utilitarianism [58]. Second, the use of financial and economic theories
Expected utility theory [73] states that if the decision maker knows
and language frames all effects of policies, including ecological impacts,
the probability fðsÞ of each state of nature, they should choose the action
as commodities that can be traded off against money [59,60].
that gives the highest expected utility, which is defined as the sum over
SCBA places boundaries with respect to whose interests count
all states of nature of the product of the state’s probability and the utility
(‘standing’); which options are to be considered; what is the time hori­
that is realised under the state, given the action chosen.
zon; and which effects are to be taken into account. With respect to
Suppose all sets and functions in Equation (1) are known: i.e. we
standing, SCBA guidelines generally recommend that only the interests
know all possible actions (A); all relevant variables (V); all possible
of national residents are to be considered (see e.g. Refs. [36–38]. This is
states of nature (S) and their probability (fðsÞ); the value of all relevant
problematic in marine systems as they often cover multiple jurisdictions,
variables under each combination of action and state of nature (cv ); and
or are otherwise linked to other marine bodies. It also raises the question
we can rank all possible outcomes by their desirability (u). Then the
how future generations are dealt with: whereas much of the literature on
problem is unpredictable, complicated, but not wicked: it can be for­
the ethics of discounting implies that future generations have standing
malised in mathematical terms and solved with methods common in
[35,61], some argue that future generations should only count as far as
operations research.
the current generation cares about them [37,62].
If f is unknown, while all possible actions (A), relevant variables (V),
SCBA also limits the number of policy alternatives to be appraised,
and states of nature (S) are known, it is impossible to calculate expected
because it is impractical to appraise all conceivable alternatives. The
utilities, but strategies to make rational decisions are still available: one
common procedure to use SCBA at different levels of precision in
can choose the action whose worst outcome (over all states of nature) is
different phases of policy development helps minimize the risk that al­
the least unfavourable, or the action with the lowest possible regret
ternatives are overlooked. The Dutch SCBA guideline [36] recommends
[72].
that the initial list of options be kept wide in order to cover the
It is also possible that different experts offer different estimates of the
parameter space as much as possible. The Dutch, UK [38], and EU [63]
probability distribution (fðsÞ) [74]. A common approach to address this
guidelines also recommend including a “minimum” option in addition to
situation is to assign each expert a probability of ‘being right’ (see e.g.
the baseline and the other policy alternatives.
Ref. [75], which would then still allow for the application of expected
In general the principle in SCBA is that the time horizon should be
utility theory. If such probabilities are not available, the problem can
long enough to cover all effects expected from the policy. In practice,
still be solved by maximizing worst outcomes or minimizing regret.
however, the recommendations vary from 10 to 30 years [63], to 10–60
So far the decision problem can be formalised as one of maximizing
years [38], to infinite [36]. This matters particularly for short time ho­
expected utility, maximizing worst outcomes, or minimizing regret. A
rizons as for longer time horizons the effect of extending the time ho­
crucial assumption, however, is that all three aforementioned sets are
rizon is also discounted more heavily.
complete: we have identified all possible actions (A), relevant variables
Lastly, some effects are not taken into account for a variety of rea­
(V), and states of nature (S). If any of these sets are not complete, the
sons, such as lack of scientific knowledge to quantify an effect, or that
problem becomes what Walker et al. [76] term “ignorance”.
the expected magnitude of the effect does not justify the costs of quan­
Decision-making under ignorance can be characterised as a truly wicked
tifying it [38]. Economic theory also dictates that effects on secondary
problem.2
markets should not be taken into account unless these markets are not
Identifying all possible actions (A) can be difficult because the
competitive [64].
availability depends not only on available technologies, but also on less
tangible factors such as social acceptability and human ingenuity. States
3.3. Wicked problems are uncertain
of nature can be interpreted broadly such that they include how different
parts of the marine system are related, and what the consequences will
3.3.1. Uncertainty and wickedness in marine governance
be of a given action on the relevant variables. Much is yet unknown
Dealing with uncertainty is a key element of coastal and marine
about the marine environment, and this lack of information rules out not
governance [65]: many relevant processes are inherently stochastic;
only the availability of probability distributions, but also a complete
observations and models are imperfect; and human responses to policies
consideration of possible outcomes. Lastly, even if all actions and their
are difficult to predict [66,67]. Ways to deal with these uncertainties,
consequences are known, our set of relevant variables (V) may be
such as Monte Carlo analysis [68] and ensemble analysis [69], require a
incomplete. The importance of particular ecosystem services, such as
great deal of knowledge and assumptions about the system to be ana­
lysed [70]. Moreover, some marine zones, such as the mesopelagic zone
[71], are so fundamentally poorly understood that there may be many
“unknown unknowns” that by definition cannot be modelled. 2
Note that an incomplete set of experts or probability distributions will not
make the problem necessarily wicked. After all, in the worst case it implies that
(f ðsÞ) is unknown, which can be dealt with formally.

4
R.A. Groeneveld Marine Policy 117 (2020) 103945

landscape quality or the presence of charismatic species, may only be Because coastal and marine zones are shared entities, conflicts be­
realised once the impacts on those qualities are experienced. tween uses and values are inevitable. Fisheries reform has to balance
notions of economic efficiency with communal values such as fairness
3.4. In wicked problems actors disagree on facts and occupational identity [85,91,95]. Notions of conservation or animal
welfare may also clash with traditions and historical use rights [86,94].
3.4.1. Conflicting beliefs and perspectives in marine governance A potential source of conflict is the growth of marine renewable
Actors can disagree on what the facts are, and on how those facts are energy (MRE). MRE is essentially a sedentary activity that requires a
to be interpreted. The emerging literature on “post-truth” suggests that degree of permanence and exclusiveness akin to private property rights
acceptance of some propositions, such as the reality of climate change or [96–98]. Other marine uses such as transport, fishing, and recreation are
the effectiveness of vaccines, depends not only on the science behind usually transient, so that their rights to marine space are less exclusive.
them, but also on other factors, including trust in the messenger [77,78]. Therefore, spatial rights granted to MRE are likely to clash with existing
For example, stakeholders disputed expert knowledge on the ecological private and public rights [96]. Resolving such conflicts involves issues
effects of powerboat races in the Dutch part of the Wadden Sea because such as fairness and justice, especially to current users.
the researchers were contracted by the organisers of the races [79]. The
initial approval by the Australian Fisheries Management Authority 3.5.2. Conflicting values in Social Cost-Benefit Analysis
(AFMA) of Seafish Australia’s trawling operations was reversed due to A fundamental assumption in SCBA is that whatever values are at
public pressure, despite being based on scientifically devised quota [80]. stake, and however they vary over actors, all relevant values are indi­
Even if basic facts are undisputed, however, actors can interpret vidual, commensurable, and substitutable. People can differ in prefer­
them differently. Different actors may adopt different frames or ences with respect to policy alternatives, but as long as the attributes of
emphasize different causal factors, risking a “blame game” between those policy alternatives can be substituted at the level of an individual,
actors [81]. For example, salmon resources in Canada’s lower Fraser an increase in income can compensate a loss in, say, the aesthetic quality
River are under pressure by different sources, including anglers and of a beach. This assumption allows cost-benefit analysts to express the
indigenous fishers, with each group pointing the finger at others while importance of environmental changes in terms of CV or EV, and to
feeling unjustly blamed for the threat to salmon stocks [82]. In Dutch eel aggregate those values over individuals [31]. Theoretically it is possible
management environmental groups and experts suggested closed fishing that actors have an infinite willingness to accept, i.e. that their loss of an
seasons as the most cost-effective means to restore depleted eel stocks, environmental attribute is so dramatic that no finite amount of money
which made fishers feel singled out as it did not address other drivers of can compensate their loss. In practice, however, such cases are avoided
stock decline [83]. or assumed away. In open-ended stated preference surveys exceptionally
high statements of willingness to accept or willingness to pay tend to be
3.4.2. Conflicting beliefs and perspectives in Social Cost-Benefit Analysis dismissed as protest bids, and the models usually estimated in
That different actors take different propositions as facts suggests that stated-choice surveys impose substitutability between attributes [99].
multiple states of nature are imaginable, i.e. different actors can assign Many of the values at stake in coastal and marine governance,
different values to the same variable or its probability distribution. The however, are shared values (see e.g. Ref. [100,101]. Unlike individual
rational economic approach to this problem is to assume that each of values, the trade-off of which can be left to individuals, shared values
these states of nature is equally valid (if not equally probable), which transcend the individual as they express an understanding of right and
implies that the problem can be approached as one of decision-making wrong at a societal level [102].
under uncertainty (see e.g. Ref. [75]. Moreover, the commensurability assumption does not hold when
This approach works as long as all perspectives and hypotheses can people hold ‘sacred’ values, such as friendship or religion, in addition to
indeed be considered legitimate. In the aforementioned cases, however, ‘secular’ values such as consumption and leisure [103]. For example,
actors do not only have differing views and hypotheses, but they also McGraw et al. [104] demonstrates that people are less likely to bargain
dispute the legitimacy of other actors or their ideas. In this situation or to look for cheaper alternatives when buying a gift for a friend or a
cost-benefit analysts and policy makers cannot avoid choosing sides in a romantic partner. Another study demonstrates that after having traded
debate that is not their expertise: either they include a controversial off nature conservation against spending money on material items,
hypothesis in their uncertainty analysis, thus legitimising it; or they people are more likely to donate money to charity as a form of moral
dismiss it, thus confirming the prevailing consensus and alienating some cleansing [105].
of the stakeholders.
If actors differ in the interpretation rather than the acceptance of 4. Conclusions and recommendations
facts, the consequentialist frame of SCBA could help focus minds on
consequences of the solution under consideration rather than the “blame This review highlights the ways in which welfare economics and its
game” [84]. But then again, actors may still interpret any given solution application to policy appraisal, Social Cost-Benefit Analysis (SCBA),
as an indictment, regardless of its efficiency. Note that this is not about assume away the characteristics of coastal and marine governance that
the distribution of costs and benefits, which can be solved by compen­ make it a ‘wicked’ problem [1,15]. The assumptions allow SCBA prac­
sation payments from ’winners’ to ’losers’, but about people feeling titioners to formulate policy decisions as constrained optimisation
unjustly targeted by a policy, which is more difficult to compensate. problems, but they also obscure considerations that may be highly
relevant to policy makers. Tracing the assumptions thus made clarifies
3.5. In wicked problems actors disagree on values the limitations of welfare-economic analysis, and at the same time it
provides a helpful benchmark to assess the ’wickedness’ of a given
3.5.1. Conflicting values in marine governance problem.
The literature on social values in fisheries demonstrates that fishers Welfare economics, or more accurately its application in SCBA, as­
are motivated not only by profit maximisation, but also by notions such sumes that the boundaries of the problem are clearly defined so that
as fishing as a way of life [85], occupational or ethnic identity [86,87], there is no ambiguity who has standing and where geographical and
or religious values [88–90]. Values such as fairness, upholding tradi­ temporal boundaries are drawn; policy alternatives should be judged by
tions, and a sense of place are part of the social fabric of fishing com­ their consequences; all possible policy alternatives, states of nature, and
munities [91,92]. Indeed, such values are not confined to fishers as other relevant criteria are known; all known facts are undisputed and if they
coastal residents also express a sense of identity and attachment to place are, at least all available beliefs are deemed equally legitimate; and all
[93,94]. values at stake regard individual, ‘secular’ values that can be

5
R.A. Groeneveld Marine Policy 117 (2020) 103945

compensated with money. These assumptions are bound to be violated as complements to SCBA.
in real life, albeit to various degrees. Marine systems often have no clear The possibility that actors hold beliefs contested by other actors
boundary so that the drawing of social, geographical, and temporal raises questions regarding the impartiality of SCBA, and the communi­
boundaries may become rather arbitrary; actors may judge policy al­ cation of its results to stakeholders and policy makers. To what extent
ternatives by other criteria than their consequences, such as whether can SCBA take a highly contested scenario into consideration without
those ‘guilty’ of the problem are properly punished; it may be uncertain legitimising it, or reversely, to what extent can practitioners decide not
whether all possible policies, outcomes, or criteria are being included in to take a scenario into consideration without disenfranchising the
the decision, i.e. there may still be ‘unknown unknowns’; actors may stakeholders who deem it likely? These questions require insights from
hold beliefs deemed illegitimate by others; and the decision may involve political science, anthropology, and social psychology. It is important to
shared values that transcend the individual, or ‘sacred’ values that realise that the issue is not just whether scientific facts are communi­
people refuse to trade off against income. Although these observations cated clearly and objectively. Recent literature suggests that beliefs may
point to limitations of SCBA, it should also be stressed that these be driven by differences in values or group loyalty rather than a disin­
simplifying assumptions are necessary to enable a consistent and intui­ terested consideration of the available evidence [115,116], so that
tive quantitative normative framework that evaluates policy alterna­ finding consensus requires an appeal to values as much as to facts.
tives by a metric common to all involved, i.e. money. Moreover, framing Lastly, the presence of shared or sacred values suggests that there are
the problem in consequentialist terms may help avoid a “blame game” limits to economic valuation, and outside those limits are values that are
[81,84]. Nevertheless, policy makers should be aware of the consider­ nevertheless important for policy makers. This raises the question how
ations not included in SCBA because of these assumptions. prevalent shared or sacred values are in coastal and marine governance,
As the assumptions underlying welfare economics and SCBA enable how they can be identified and distinguished from individual, secular
practitioners to treat coastal and marine governance as a ‘tame’ con­ values, and how they should be dealt with in public decision-making
strained optimisation problem, they can also help define more sharply processes. The presence of sacred values has so far been investigated
what makes a problem truly wicked. Rather than defining a wicked through behavioural experiments (see e.g. Ref. [104], stated choice
problem, it may more helpful to employ welfare economics to define surveys [117], and focus group discussions [118]. These methods need
what makes a problem tame: (1) its definition is unambiguous; (2) all to be applied to a variety of cases to understand the prevalence and
available policy options, possible outcomes, and relevant criteria are importance of sacred values in coastal and marine governance. Dealing
known, even if their probability distribution is unknown; (3) all facts are with sacred values in policy appraisal raises the question to what extent
universally accepted, or if not, all available beliefs are commonly trade-offs can be reframed in a way that allows for monetisation,
deemed legitimate; (4) all actors accept consequentialism as a moral whether monetary valuation (and hence SCBA) should be strictly limited
guide; and (5) all values at stake are individual and ‘secular’, i.e. can be to secular values, and how deliberative valuation procedures can pro­
compensated with and traded off against income. If these criteria are vide a richer insight into the values at stake [100,119,120].
met, then there is little left to make the problem ‘wicked’. Of course no Unavoidably, tracing the limitations and assumptions of welfare
realistic policy issue meets all these criteria, but it is likely that some economics and its application in SCBA emphasizes it weakness and may
problems violate more criteria, and given criteria to a greater extent, give the impression that its use as a policy appraisal tool should be
than others. The assumptions underlying welfare economics discussed in avoided. On the contrary, this review demonstrates one of the strengths
this review can be helpful in understanding what exactly makes a of welfare economics and SCBA: economists and legal scholars make its
problem wicked, to what extent it is wicked, and what policy appraisal assumptions explicit, so that they can be criticised and tested. This lends
tools and decision-making procedures are needed to select policies to SCBA a clarity that enables practitioners to delineate which consider­
address the problem. ations are included and which ones are not. It is the same clarity that
The discussion of welfare economics and wicked problems in this makes welfare economics a helpful benchmark to determine the wick­
review raises a number of open research questions in each of the four edness of a given problem. Nevertheless, there is plenty of scope to
categories of wickedness. Regarding the definition and delineation of improve the application of SCBA in coastal and marine governance, and
the policy problem, how does SCBA as a policy appraisal tool interact particularly in how it is embedded in the overall public decision-making
with the wider political decision-making process? To what extent do process.
political considerations impact the delineation of a given SCBA, and to
what extent does this determine its outcomes? There is some literature CRediT authorship contribution statement
on how SCBA is used by policy makers, and how it changes their de­
cisions, especially for infrastructure (see e.g. Ref. [106–108] and envi­ Rolf A. Groeneveld: Conceptualization, Investigation, Writing -
ronmental policy (see e.g. Ref. [109–111]. To what extent the insights of original draft, Writing - review & editing.
this literature extend to typical marine issues, such as marine spatial
planning and fisheries policy, is yet unclear. Lastly, the possible role of
Acknowledgements
SCBA as a conflict-solving tool by putting problems in a rational, con­
sequentialist frame [84] yet needs to be tested in a wider range of cases.
Helpful comments from Katrien Termeer, Art Dewulf, Simon Bush,
Regarding uncertainty, it is unlikely that SCBA itself can be improved
Hans-Peter Weikard, and an anonymous reviewer are gratefully
to deal with the possibility that the set of policy alternatives, states of
acknowledged. All remaining errors are the sole responsibility of the
nature, or relevant criteria is incomplete, but solutions may be possible
author.
in the wider decision-making process in which SCBA is embedded, or in
complementary tools to explore and evaluate alternatives and outcomes.
Appendix A. Supplementary data
Such complementary tools should employ the variety of views and
values among stakeholders in order to cast a wide net and maximize the
Supplementary data to this article can be found online at https://doi.
likelihood that all relevant alternatives, outcomes, and criteria are
org/10.1016/j.marpol.2020.103945.
covered. Hence including a variety of stakeholders in policy design and
appraisal is essential [112,113]. Once possible outcomes have been
identified, a possible tool to assess their plausibility is Future-Perfect References
Thinking [114], where a specific future or event is assumed, and the
[1] S. Jentoft, R. Chuenpagdee, Fisheries and coastal governance as a wicked
mechanisms that may lead to that particular outcome are traced back to problem, Mar. Pol. 33 (2009) 553–560.
the present. So far, however, these methods have been largely untested [2] OECD, The Ocean Economy in 2030, OECD Publishing, 2016.

6
R.A. Groeneveld Marine Policy 117 (2020) 103945

[3] M.D. Adler, E.A. Posner, Rethinking cost-benefit analysis, Yale Law J. 109 (1999) [41] EU, Directive 2000/60/EC of the European Parliament and of the Council of 23
165–246. October 2000 establishing a framework for Community action in the field of
[4] G. Atkinson, S. Mourato, Environmental cost-benefit analysis, Annu. Rev. water policy, Off. J. Eur. Union. (2000) 327.
Environ. Resour. 33 (2008) 317–344. [42] EU, Directive 2008/56/EC of the European Parliament and of the council of 17
[5] C. Bertram, T. Dworak, S. G€ orlitz, E. Interwies, K. Rehdanz, Cost-benefit analysis June 2008 establishing a framework for community action in the field of marine
in the context of the EU Marine Strategy Framework Directive: the case of environmental policy (Marine Strategy Framework Directive), Off. J. Eur. Union.
Germany, Mar. Pol. 43 (2014) 307–312. (2008). L 164/19.
[6] N. Hanley, S. Hynes, D. Patterson, N. Jobsvogt, Economic valuation of marine and [43] T. B€orger, N.J. Beaumont, L. Pendleton, K.J. Boyle, P. Cooper, S. Fletcher,
coastal ecosystems: is it currently fit for purpose? J. Ocean Coastal Econ. 2 T. Haab, M. Hanemann, T.L. Hooper, S.S. Hussain, R. Portela, M. Stithou,
(2015), 1. J. Stockill, T. Taylor, M.C. Austen, Incorporating ecosystem services in marine
[7] P.C. Roebeling, C.D. Coelho, E.M. Reis, Coastal erosion and coastal defense planning: the role of valuation, Mar. Pol. 46 (2014) 161–170.
interventions: a cost-benefit analysis, J. Coast Res. (2011) 1415–1419. [44] T.-Y. Lai, J. Salminen, J.-P. J€
appinen, S. Koljonen, L. Mononen, E. Nieminen,
[8] C. Andr�e, D. Boulet, H. Rey-Valette, B. Rulleau, Protection by hard defence P. Vihervaara, S. Oinonen, Bridging the gap between ecosystem service indicators
structures or relocation of assets exposed to coastal risks: contributions and and ecosystem accounting in Finland, Ecol. Model. 377 (2018) 51–65.
drawbacks of cost-benefit analysis for long-term adaptation choices to climate [45] T. Wang, G.-s. He, Q.-l. Zhou, J.-z. Gao, L.-j. Deng, Designing a framework for
change, Ocean Coast Manag. 134 (2016) 173–182. marine ecosystem assets accounting, Ocean Coast Manag. 163 (2018) 92–100.
[9] T. Haer, W.J. Botzen, J. Zavala-Hidalgo, C. Cusell, P.J. Ward, Economic [46] W. Chen, K.A.M. Van Assche, S. Hynes, T. Bekkby, H.C. Christie, H. Gundersen,
evaluation of climate risk adaptation strategies: cost-benefit analysis of flood Ecosystem accounting’s potential to support coastal and marine governance, Mar.
protection in Tabasco, Mexico, Atm� osfera 30 (2017) 101–120. Pol 112 (2020) 103758.
[10] D. Hatton MacDonald, A. Ardeshiri, J.M. Rose, B.D. Russell, S.D. Connell, Valuing [47] A. Dvarskas, Experimental ecosystem accounting for coastal and marine areas: a
coastal water quality: Adelaide, south Australia Metropolitan area, Mar. Pol. 52 pilot application of the SEEA-EEA in Long Island coastal bays, Mar. Pol. 100
(2015) 116–124. (2019) 141–151.
[11] J.R. Wakefield, K. Myers, Social cost benefit analysis for deep sea minerals [48] A. Ruijs, M. Vardon, S. Bass, S. Ahlroth, Natural capital accounting for better
mining, Mar. Pol. 95 (2018) 346–355. policy, Ambio 48 (2019) 714–725.
[12] S.E. Rees, M.J. Attrill, M.C. Austen, S.C. Mangi, L.D. Rodwell, A thematic cost- [49] M.W. Kreuter, C. De Rosa, E.H. Howze, G.T. Baldwin, Understanding wicked
benefit analysis of a marine protected area, J. Environ. Manag. 114 (2013) problems: a key to advancing environmental health promotion, Health Educ.
476–485. Behav. 31 (2004) 441–454.
[13] N. Pascal, A. Brathwaite, L. Brander, A. Seidl, M. Philip, E. Clua, Evidence of [50] D. Jolley, K.M. Douglas, The effects of anti-vaccine conspiracy theories on
economic benefits for public investment in MPAs, Ecosyst. Serv. 30 (2018) 3–13. vaccination intentions, PloS One 9 (2014), e89177.
[14] B. Snyder, M.J. Kaiser, Ecological and economic cost-benefit analysis of offshore [51] M. Motta, T. Callaghan, S. Sylvester, Knowing less but presuming more: Dunning-
wind energy, Renew. Energy 34 (2009) 1567–1578. Kruger effects and the endorsement of anti-vaccine policy attitudes, Soc. Sci. Med.
[15] H.W.J. Rittel, M.M. Webber, Dilemmas in a general theory of planning, Pol. Sci. 4 211 (2018) 274–281.
(1973) 155–169. [52] J. Tosun, S. Schaub, Mobilization in the European public sphere: the struggle over
[16] A.S. Khan, B. Neis, The rebuilding imperative in fisheries: clumsy solutions for a genetically modified organisms, Rev. Pol. Res. 34 (2017) 310–330.
wicked problem? Prog. Oceanogr. 87 (2010) 347–356. [53] A.M. McCright, R.E. Dunlap, Cool dudes: the denial of climate change among
[17] S.C. Moser, S.J. Williams, D.F. Boesch, Wicked challenges at land’s end: managing conservative white males in the United States, Global Environ. Change 21 (2011)
coastal vulnerability under climate change, Annu. Rev. Environ. Resour. 37 1163–1172.
(2012) 51–78. [54] J. Lacey, M. Howden, C. Cvitanovic, R.M. Colvin, Understanding and managing
[18] T.P. Hughes, H. Huang, M.A.L. Young, The wicked problem of China’s trust at the climate science-policy interface, Nat. Clim. Change 8 (2018) 22–28.
disappearing coral reefs, Conserv. Biol. 27 (2013) 261–269. [55] N.G. Mankiw, M.P. Taylor, Economics, Thomson Learning, London, 2006.
[19] H.T. Sandersen, I. Kvalvik, Access to aquaculture sites: a wicked problem in [56] S.B. Longo, R. Clausen, The tragedy of the commodity: the overexploitation of the
Norwegian aquaculture development, Mar. Stud. 14 (2015), 10. Mediterranean bluefin tuna fishery, Organ. Environ. 24 (2011) 312–328.
[20] J. Alford, B.W. Head, Wicked and less wicked problems: a typology and a [57] C. B�en�
e, When fishery rhymes with poverty: a first step beyond the old paradigm
contingency framework, Policy Soc. 36 (2017) 397–413. on poverty in small-scale fisheries, World Dev. 31 (2003) 949–975.
[21] B.G. Peters, What is so wicked about wicked problems? A conceptual analysis and [58] S. Smilansky, Utilitarianism and the ’punishment’ of the innocent: the general
a research program, Policy Soc. 36 (2017) 385–396. problem, Analysis 50 (1990) 256–261.
[22] N. Turnbull, R. Hoppe, Problematizing "wickedness": a critique of the wicked [59] D.J. McCauley, Selling out on nature, Nature 443 (2006) 27–28.
problems concept, from philosophy to practice, Policy Soc. 38 (2019) 315–337. [60] E. G�omez-Baggethun, M. Ruiz-P� erez, Economic valuation and the
[23] T. B€orger, S. Broszeit, H. Ahtiainen, J.P. Atkins, D. Burdon, T. Luisetti, commodification of ecosystem services, Prog. Phys. Geogr.: Earth Environ. 35
A. Murillas, S. Oinonen, L. Paltriguera, L. Roberts, M.C. Uyarra, M.C. Austen, (2011) 613–628.
Assessing costs and benefits of measures to achieve good environmental status in [61] N. Stern, The economics of climate change, Am. Econ. Rev. 98 (2008) 1–37.
European regional seas: challenges, opportunities, and lessons learnt, Front. Mar. [62] D. Whittington, D. MacRae, The issue of standing in cost-benefit analysis, J. Pol.
Sci. 3 (2016), 192-192. Anal. Manag. 5 (1986) 665–682.
[24] S. Oinonen, T. B€ orger, S. Hynes, A.K. Buchs, A.-S. Heiskanen, K. Hyyti€ ainen, [63] D. Sartori, G. Catalano, M. Genco, C. Pancotti, E. Sirtori, S. Vignetti, C. Del Bo,
T. Luisetti, R. van der Veeren, The role of economics in ecosystem based Guide to Cost-Benefit Analysis of Investment Projects: Economic Appraisal Tool
management: the case of the EU Marine Strategy Framework Directive. First for Cohesion Policy 2014-2020, European Commission, Directorate-General for
lessons learnt and way forward, J. Ocean Coastal Econ. 2 (2016), 3. Regional and Urban policy, Brussels, 2014.
[25] C. Torres, N. Hanley, Communicating research on the economic valuation of [64] A.E. Boardman, D.H. Greenberg, A.R. Vining, D.L. Weimer, Cost-benefit Analysis:
coastal and marine ecosystem services, Mar. Pol. 75 (2017) 99–107. Concepts and Practice, fourth ed., Prentice Hall, Upper Saddle River, 2011.
[26] S.S. Batie, Wicked problems and applied economics, Am. J. Agric. Econ. 90 [65] L.W. Botsford, J.C. Castilla, C.H. Peterson, The management of fisheries and
(2008) 1176–1191. marine ecosystems, Science 277 (1997) 509–515.
[27] W. Beckerman, Utilitarianism: the Search for an Overriding Value. Economics as [66] J. Harwood, K. Stokes, Coping with uncertainty in ecological advice: lessons from
Applied Ethics, Springer International Publishing, 2017, pp. 93–103. fisheries, Trends Ecol. Evol. 18 (2003) 617–622.
[28] A. Sen, Utilitarianism and welfarism, J. Philos. 76 (1979) 463–489. [67] E.A. Fulton, A.D.M. Smith, D.C. Smith, I.E. van Putten, Human behaviour: the key
[29] P. Singer, Animal Liberation: a New Ethics for Our Treatment of Animals, Cape, source of uncertainty in fisheries management, Fish Fish. 12 (2011) 2–17.
London, 1976. [68] D.S. Butterworth, N. Bentley, J.A.A. De Oliveira, G.P. Donovan, L.T. Kell, A.
[30] D. Pearce, Cost benefit analysis and environmental policy, Oxf. Rev. Econ. Pol. 14 M. Parma, A.E. Punt, K.J. Sainsbury, A.D.M. Smith, T.K. Stokes, Purported flaws
(1998) 84–100. in management strategy evaluation: basic problems or misinterpretations? ICES
[31] M.D. Adler, Benefit-cost analysis and distributional weights: an overview, Rev. (Int. Counc. Explor. Sea) J. Mar. Sci. 67 (2010) 567–574.
Environ. Econ. Pol. 10 (2016) 264–285. [69] D.S. Kolody, J.P. Eveson, R.M. Hillary, Modelling growth in tuna RFMO stock
[32] J.R. Hicks, Foundations of welfare economics, Econ. J. 49 (1939) 696–712. assessments: current approaches and challenges, Fish. Res. 180 (2016) 177–193.
[33] N. Kaldor, Welfare propositions of economics and interpersonal comparisons of [70] M.-J. Rochet, J.C. Rice, Simulation-based management strategy evaluation:
utility, Econ. J. 49 (1939) 549–552. ignorance disguised as mathematics? ICES (Int. Counc. Explor. Sea) J. Mar. Sci.
[34] N. Stern, C. Taylor, Climate change: risk, ethics, and the Stern review, Science 66 (2009) 754–762.
317 (2007) 203–204. [71] M.A. St John, A. Borja, G. Chust, M. Heath, I. Grigorov, P. Mariani, A.P. Martin, R.
[35] P. Dasgupta, Discounting climate change, J. Risk Uncertain. 37 (2008) 141–169. S. Santos, A dark hole in our understanding of marine ecosystems and their
[36] G. Romijn, G. Renes, General Guidance for Cost-Benefit Analysis, CPB/PBL, The services: perspectives from the mesopelagic community, Front. Mar. Sci. 3
Hague, 2013. (2016), 31.
[37] The Treasury, Guide to Social Cost-Benefit Analysis, The Treasury, New Zealand [72] L.A. Cox, Confronting deep uncertainties in risk analysis, Risk Anal. 32 (2012)
Government, 2015. 1607–1629.
[38] Her Majesty’s Treasury, The Green Book: Central Government Guidance on [73] J. von Neumann, O. Morgenstern, Theory of Games and Economic Behaviour,
Appraisal and Evaluation, Her Majesty’s Treasury, London, 2018. second ed., Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1944.
[39] R. van der Veeren, Different cost-benefit analyses in The Netherlands for the [74] A. Dewulf, M. Craps, R. Bouwen, T. Taillieu, C. Pahl-Wostl, Integrated
European Water Framework Directive, Water Pol. 12 (2010) 746–760. management of natural resources: dealing with ambiguous issues, multiple actors
[40] W.J. Clinton, Executive order 12866 of September 30, 1993: regulatory planning and diverging frames, Water Sci. Technol. 52 (2005) 115–124.
and review, Fed. Regist. 58 (1993).

7
R.A. Groeneveld Marine Policy 117 (2020) 103945

[75] S. Athanassoglou, V. Bosetti, Setting environmental policy when experts disagree, [97] G. Wright, A.M. O’Hagan, J. de Groot, Y. Leroy, N. Soininen, R. Salcido, M. Abad
Environ. Resour. Econ. 61 (2015) 497–516. Castelos, S. Jude, J. Rochette, S. Kerr, Establishing a legal research agenda for
[76] W.E. Walker, R.J. Lempert, J.H. Kwakkel, Deep Uncertainty, in: S.I. Gass, M.C. Fu ocean energy, Mar. Pol. 63 (2016) 126–134.
(Eds.), Encyclopedia of Operations Research and Management Science, Springer [98] L.D. Jenkins, S.J. Dreyer, H.J. Polis, E. Beaver, A.A. Kowalski, H.L. Linder, T.
US, Boston, MA, 2013, pp. 395–402. N. McMillin, K.L. McTiernan, T.T. Rogier, L.E. Wiesebron, Human dimensions of
[77] S. Lewandowsky, K. Oberauer, Motivated rejection of science, Curr. Dir. Psychol. tidal energy: a review of theories and frameworks, Renew. Sustain. Energy Rev.
Sci. 25 (2016) 217–222. 97 (2018) 323–337.
[78] S. Lewandowsky, U.K.H. Ecker, J. Cook, Beyond misinformation: understanding [99] T.C. Haab, K.E. McConnell, Valuing Environmental and Natural Resources: the
and coping with the "Post-Truth" era, J. Appl. Res. Mem. Cogn. 6 (2017) 353–369. Econometrics of Non-market Valuation, Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, UK, 2002.
[79] J.R. Floor, C.S.A. van Koppen, J.P.M. van Tatenhove, Uncertainties in the [100] J.O. Kenter, L. O’Brien, N. Hockley, N. Ravenscroft, I. Fazey, K.N. Irvine, M.
assessment of “significant effect” on the Dutch Natura 2000 Wadden Sea site: the S. Reed, M. Christie, E. Brady, R. Bryce, A. Church, N. Cooper, A. Davies, A. Evely,
mussel seed fishery and powerboat race controversies, Environ. Sci. Pol. 55 M. Everard, R. Fish, J.A. Fisher, N. Jobstvogt, C. Molloy, J. Orchard-Webb,
(2016) 380–392. S. Ranger, M. Ryan, V. Watson, S. Williams, What are shared and social values of
[80] H. Murphy-Gregory, Governance via persuasion: environmental NGOs and the ecosystems? Ecol. Econ. 111 (2015) 86–99.
social licence to operate, Environ. Polit. 27 (2017) 320–340. [101] K.N. Irvine, L. O’Brien, N. Ravenscroft, N. Cooper, M. Everard, I. Fazey, M.
[81] S. Jentoft, R. Chuenpagdee, Concerns and Problems in Fisheries and Aquaculture S. Reed, J.O. Kenter, Ecosystem services and the idea of shared values, Ecosyst.
– Exploring Governability, Governability of Fisheries and Aquaculture: Theory and Serv. 21 (2016) 184–193.
Applications, Springer Netherlands, Dordrecht, 2013, pp. 33–44. [102] M. Sagoff, Values and preferences, Ethics 96 (1986) 301–316.
[82] V.M. Nguyen, N. Young, S.G. Hinch, S.J. Cooke, Getting past the blame game: [103] P.E. Tetlock, B.A. Mellers, J.P. Scoblic, Sacred versus pseudo-sacred values: how
convergence and divergence in perceived threats to salmon resources among people cope with taboo trade-offs, Am. Econ. Rev. 107 (2017) 96–99.
anglers and indigenous fishers in Canada’s lower Fraser River, Ambio 45 (2016) [104] A.P. McGraw, D.F. Davis, S.E. Scott, P.E. Tetlock, The price of not putting a price
591–601. on love, Judg. Dec. Making 11 (2016) 40–47.
[83] M.L. van Herten, H.A.C. Runhaar, Dialogues of the deaf in Dutch eel management [105] B. Stikvoort, T. Lindahl, T.M. Daw, Thou shalt not sell nature: how taboo trade-
policy. Explaining controversy and deadlock with argumentative discourse offs can make us act pro-environmentally, to clear our conscience, Ecol. Econ. 129
analysis, J. Environ. Plann. Manag. 56 (2013) 1002–1020. (2016) 252–259.
[84] C.R. Sunstein, Is cost–benefit analysis a foreign language? Quart. J. Exper. Psych [106] J. Eliasson, M. Lundberg, Do cost-benefit analyses influence transport investment
72 (2019) 3–7. decisions? Experiences from the Swedish transport investment plan 2010-21,
[85] T.G. Acott, J. Urquhart, Co-constructing cultural ecosystem services and Transport Rev. 32 (2012) 29–48.
wellbeing through a place-based approach, in: D.S. Johnson, T.G. Acott, [107] J.A. Annema, K. Frenken, C. Koopmans, M. Kroesen, Relating cost-benefit analysis
N. Stacey, J. Urquhart (Eds.), Social Wellbeing and the Values of Small-Scale results with transport project decisions in The Netherlands, Lett. Spatial Resour.
Fisheries, Springer, Cham, Switzerland, 2018, pp. 23–44. Sci. 10 (2017) 109–127.
[86] R. van Ginkel, Killing giants of the sea: contentious heritage and the politics of [108] N. Mouter, Dutch politicians’ use of cost-benefit analysis, Transportation 44
culture, J. Mediterr. Stud. 15 (2005) 71–98. (2017) 1127–1145.
[87] N. Stacey, D.J. Steenbergen, J. Clifton, G. Acciaioli, Understanding social [109] N. Hanley, Cost-benefit analysis and environmental policymaking, Environ.
wellbeing and values of small-scale fisheries amongst the Sama-Bajau of Plann. C Govern. Pol. 19 (2001) 103–118.
archipelagic Southeast Asia, in: D.S. Johnson, T.G. Acott, N. Stacey, J. Urquhart [110] A. Dehnhardt, The influence of interests and beliefs on the use of environmental
(Eds.), Social Wellbeing and the Values of Small-Scale Fisheries, Springer, Cham, cost-benefit analysis in water policy: the case of German policy-makers,
Switzerland, 2018, pp. 97–124. Environm. Policy Gover. 24 (2014) 391–404.
[88] A.D. Rijnsdorp, W. Dol, M. Hoyer, M.A. Pastoors, Effects of fishing power and [111] S. Feuillette, H. Levrel, B. Boeuf, S. Blanquart, O. Gorin, G. Monaco, B. Penisson,
competitive interactions among vessels on the effort allocation on the trip level of S. Robichon, The use of cost-benefit analysis in environmental policies: some
the Dutch beam trawl fleet, ICES (Int. Counc. Explor. Sea) J. Mar. Sci. 57 (2000) issues raised by the Water Framework Directive implementation in France,
927–937. Environ. Sci. Pol. 57 (2016) 79–85.
[89] L.E. Chimello de Oliveira, F. Berkes, What value S~ ao Pedro’s procession? [112] D.J. Snowden, M.E. Boone, A leader’s framework for decision making, Harv. Bus.
Ecosystem services from local people’s perceptions, Ecol. Econ. 107 (2014) Rev. 85 (2007) 69–75.
114–121. [113] D. Swanson, S. Barg, S. Tyler, H. Venema, S. Tomar, S. Bhadwal, S. Nair, D. Roy,
[90] G. Lokuge, M. Munas, Risk, reciprocity and solidarity: the moral economy of J. Drexhage, Seven tools for creating adaptive policies, Technol. Forecast. Soc.
fishing in Trincomalee, Sri Lanka, in: D.S. Johnson, T.G. Acott, N. Stacey, Change 77 (2010) 924–939.
J. Urquhart (Eds.), Social Wellbeing and the Values of Small-Scale Fisheries, [114] L. Fuglsang, J. Mattsson, Making sense of innovation: a future perfect approach,
Springer, Cham, Switzerland, 2018, pp. 243–266. J. Manag. Organ. 17 (2015) 448–458.
[91] F. Berkes, P.K. Nayak, Role of communities in fisheries management: “one would [115] D.M. Kahan, Ideology, motivated reasoning, and cognitive reflection, Judg. Dec.
first need to imagine it”, Mar. Stud. 17 (2018) 241–251. Making 8 (2013) 407–424.
[92] D.S. Johnson, The values of small-scale fisheries, in: D.S. Johnson, T.G. Acott, [116] R. B�enabou, J. Tirole, Mindful economics: the production, consumption, and
N. Stacey, J. Urquhart (Eds.), Social Wellbeing and the Values of Small-Scale value of beliefs, J. Econ. Perspect. 30 (2016) 141–164.
Fisheries, Springer, Cham, Switzerland, 2018, pp. 1–21. [117] C.G. Chorus, B. Pud� ane, N. Mouter, D. Campbell, Taboo trade-off aversion: a
[93] S.C. Klain, T.A. Satterfield, K.M.A. Chan, What matters and why? Ecosystem discrete choice model and empirical analysis, J. Choice Model. 27 (2018) 37–49.
services and their bundled qualities, Ecol. Econ. 107 (2014) 310–320. [118] T.M. Daw, S. Coulthard, W.W.L. Cheung, K. Brown, C. Abunge, D. Galafassi, G.
[94] M. Voyer, N. Gollan, K. Barclay, W. Gladstone, ’It’s part of me’: understanding the D. Peterson, T.R. McClanahan, J.O. Omukoto, L. Munyi, Evaluating taboo trade-
values, images and principles of coastal users and their influence on the social offs in ecosystems services and human well-being, in: Proceedings of the National
acceptability of MPAs, Mar. Pol. 52 (2015) 93–102. Academy of Sciences, vol. 112, 2015, pp. 6949–6954.
[95] C. Carothers, Fisheries privatization, social transitions, and well-being in Kodiak, [119] S. Parks, J. Gowdy, What have economists learned about valuing nature? A
Alaska, Mar. Pol. 61 (2015) 313–322. review essay, Ecosyst. Serv. 3 (2013) e1–e10.
[96] S. Kerr, J. Colton, K. Johnson, G. Wright, Rights and ownership in sea country: [120] S. Martino, P. Tett, J. Kenter, The interplay between economics, legislative power
implications of marine renewable energy for indigenous and local communities, and social influence examined through a social-ecological framework for marine
Mar. Pol. 52 (2015) 108–115. ecosystems services, Sci. Total Environ. 651 (2019) 1388–1404.

Вам также может понравиться