Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 18

STANGHELLINI / PSYCHOPATHOLOGY OF COMMON SENSE ■ 201

Psychopathology of
Common Sense
Giovanni Stanghellini

ABSTRACT: It is well established by psychopathological KEYWORDS: antagonomia, attitude, attunement, com-


research that disorders of self-experience are among mon sense, intuition, schizophrenia, self, social knowl-
the main features of schizophrenic prodromes in a edge, vulnerability
pathogenetic sense. Disorders of the phenomenal self,
as “lack of ipseity” (the vanishing of the feeling of Tandis que les autres sens nous mettent en rapport
being embedded in oneself and of distinctiveness be- avec des choses, le bon sens préside à nos rélations
tween the self and the outer world) and “hyper-reflex- avec des personnes.
ivity” (the monitoring of one’s own life entailing the —Henry Bergson
tendency to objectify parts of one’s own self in an
outer space) are considered key phenomena of schizo-
phrenic vulnerability. In this paper, I argue that the Introduction
analyses of the disorders of phenomenal self catch
only some dimensions of schizophrenic vulnerability,
since they mainly focus on the pathological changes in

A
subjective experience of an isolated self and disregard N ESTABLISHED THEORY in the phenomeno-
the fact that the self is not purely personal. Because logical tradition is that the key vulnera-
our existence is fundamentally tied to a social exist-
bility factor predisposing to schizophrenic
ence, the feeling of one’s own self and the sense of
“reality” of an experience are products of intersubjec- breakdown is what is generally called a “crisis of
tivity and not only a private process based on intro- common sense,” that is, a loss of the meaning
spection or reflexivity in which one is engaged in an and significance that we usually attach without
idiosyncratic way. Building on, and extending, contri- conscious reflection to everyday objects and situ-
butions of the phenomenological tradition, I attempt ations and to relationships with other persons. It
to demonstrate that intuitive attunement is the basic is usually assumed that the primary characteris-
prerequisite for establishing one’s sense of “reality”
tic of common sense is in subject-object attune-
(feeling familiarly related to one’s environment) and
for establishing one’s sense of “ipseity” (the sense of ment. In this paper, I argue that the crisis of
existing as a subject of awareness). In the last part of common sense is in fact a consequence of a more
the paper, I show the importance of the concepts fundamental disturbance of intersubjectivity, i.e.,
“lack of attunement” and “antagonomia” (the rejec- that the primary disturbance is not in the attune-
tion of conventional knowledge and intuitive attune- ment between subject and object, but in the at-
ment, experienced as dangerous sources of loss of tunement between subject and subject (or self-
individuality) to establish a comprehensive theory of
other attunement).
schizophrenic vulnerability. I finally discuss the impli-
cations of this view for empirical research and clinical I have elsewhere (Stanghellini 2000a) devel-
management of schizophrenic vulnerability. oped a model of vulnerability to schizophrenic

© 2002 by The Johns Hopkins University Press


202 ■ PPP / VOL. 8, NO. 2–3 / JUNE–SEPTEMBER 2001

breakdown based on three key elements: sensory, of causality seems to go from interpersonal diffi-
typification, and attitudinal disorders. Of these, culties to the schizophrenic syndrome as a whole.
it is mainly the attitudinal element (see also Stang- Others (Bleuler 1922; Kretschmer 1922;
hellini 2000b), which is essential to the subject- Minkowski 1927; Blankenburg 1971; Kraus
subject attunement, and it is on this that I con- 1977; Parnas and Bovet 1991; Cutting 1997)
centrate in this paper. The attitudinal level of consider impairments in the area of interperson-
schizophrenic vulnerability is analyzed as a skep- al competence not just as an outcome of psychot-
tical attitude towards common sense and a height- ic syndromes, but also as a fundamental phe-
ened tolerance of ambiguity. The characteristics of nomenon of psychotic (schizophrenic and
these phenomena are described in two detailed manic-depressive) vulnerability. Critics of DSM-
clinical reports and exemplified in a number of IV’s pseudo-atheoretical and syndromatological
case vignettes. The implications of this argument approach to the diagnosis of schizophrenia main-
for theoretical and empirical research in psycho- tain that, although we lack established criteria to
pathology and for management are discussed. define the core features of schizophrenia, none-
It is a matter of debate whether abnormalities theless, we feel, or intuit, the existence of a basic
in interpersonal and social competence in pre- relational deficit characterizing schizophrenic
schizophrenic people are simply correlates or con- patients (Maj 1998). However, we are at odds
sequences of mild psychotic symptoms or, rather, when we try to define this “deficit” reliably. Despite
risk factors in a pathogenetical sense. DSM-IV the clinical and theoretical importance attribut-
quite vaguely states that schizophrenia “involves” ed to the interpersonal deficit in schizophrenia,
dysfunctions in interpersonal relations (APA we still know very little about its components
1994, Criterion B). To involve means to include and about what contributes to establishing it.
as a part of a whole, with no pathogenetical Here we are confronted with a puzzling di-
implication, and to imply or entail in a causal lemma: Should we fully depend on our pre-con-
sense. In the former sense, social dysfunctions ceptual apprehension or should we attempt to
are seen as just co-occurring with other schizo- pin down our impressions and make abstract but
phrenic symptoms such as psychotic symptoms; verifiable criteria from them? If we do not want
in the latter, social dysfunctions are interpreted to renounce using non-operationalized but far-
as consequences of the schizophrenic syndrome, reaching concepts focusing on the psychotic’s
although not as direct results of any other single attitude towards his social environment—such
feature. as the schizoid/syntonic distinction (Bleuler 1922;
Several studies have suggested that lack of Minkowski 1927) or the schizoid/cycloid con-
social competence may be an early sign of schizo- ceptual couple (Kretschmer 1922)—through
phrenic vulnerability (Parnas et al. 1982; Parnas which classic psychopathology catches the core
and Jorgensen 1989; Resch 1992; Dworkin et al. of schizophrenic and manic-depressive vulnera-
1993; Dworkin et al. 1994; Hodges et al. 1999), bilities, we should aim at making them compati-
even in the absence of other symptoms. Some ble with conceptual and empirical testing.
authors (Broks 1997; Malmberg et al. 1998)
hypothesize that schizophrenia can be construed Disorders of the Phenomenal
essentially as a disorder of social cognition (Penn Self in Early Schizophrenia
et al. 1997), i.e., a disorder of the accurate per-
ception of the dispositions and intentions of oth- The recognition of the subjective experiences
er individuals (Brothers 1992), and that the rela- provides the basis for psychopathological research
tionship between interpersonal difficulties and on psychoses (Lieberman 1983). Phenomenal dis-
schizophrenia may be causal, since interpersonal orders of the self are, since Jaspers (1997), the
difficulties may be the only predictors of future primary concern of phenomenological psycho-
psychotic breakdowns (Malmberg et al. 1998). pathology, which is primarily a study of abnor-
Accordingly, it can be argued that the direction mal conscious phenomena.
STANGHELLINI / PSYCHOPATHOLOGY OF COMMON SENSE ■ 203

In everyday experience, we use the word “self” Hyper-Reflexivity. Reflexivity is the process
to define the singularity we each feel ourselves to through which I take a part of myself, especially
be, the site from which we perceive the world of my mental life, as an object of awareness.
and from which we act (Harré 1998). We all Schizophrenics, as Sass (1992) has demonstrat-
have a sense of our own self. We often view our ed, tend to become hyper-reflexive, that is, to be
self as an enduring structure in which our basic increasingly engaged in monitoring their own life
characteristics (ideas, affects, mental processes, (especially mental life). This accompanies a lack
etc.) are stored or at least as a rather stable of fluidity in actions such as so-called loss of
representation of our own personal identity automatic actions. Mental phenomena that would
(Strawson 1999). The phenomenal self is the self usually be sensed as part of the self are objecti-
immediately given in subjective experience. My fied, spatialized, that is, felt as existing in an
phenomenal self is my present experience of my “outer” space. They become objects of focal
own body and of the mental events occurring in awareness. For instance, thoughts are felt in some
this moment (i.e., thoughts, emotions, feelings), special part of the brain.
including perceptions of the outer world, memo- In short, in schizophrenic prodromes, lack of
ries of the past, and my projections into the future. ipseity entails the lack of the feeling of distinc-
It was well established by qualitative (Jan- tiveness between the self and the outer world—a
zarik 1959; Conrad 1966) and quantitative sensation of fuzziness and feebleness of my being
(Chapman 1966; Huber 1966) research that dis- present. Hyper-reflexivity entails spatialization
orders of self-experience are among the main of one’s own bodily and mental phenomena—
features of schizophrenic prodromes in a patho- parts of my own self become like things in an
genetical sense. Researchers have emphasized the outer space.
relevance of auto-, somato-, and allo-psychic de-
personalization phenomena—i.e., strange changes Disorders of the Social Self
in self-awareness in which the person feels as if
he and/or the external environment is unreal— The analyses of the disorders of phenomenal
for the pathogenesis of full-blown psychotic symp- self catch only some (although fundamental) di-
toms (Klosterkoetter 1988). Recently, Parnas et mensions of schizophrenic vulnerability. Disor-
al. (1998) have reconceptualized pre-schizophren- ders of self-awareness mainly consider the per-
ic self-disorders within a phenomenological son as an isolated self and may disregard the fact
framework and classified them in the following that the self is not purely personal. Our existence
two main categories: is fundamentally tied to a social existence—the
phenomenon of intersubjectivity. My sense of
Transformations of Ipseity. Ipseity (Henry presence derives from the way I constitute myself
2000) is the pre-reflective modality of self-aware- and the world in social situations. The sense of
ness. It is the feeling of swimming like a fish and “reality” of an experience and the definition of
being present in water, of which I become aware one’s own self are products of intersubjectivity
only when it is lacking. This sense is pre-reflec- (Berger and Luckmann 1966).
tive—it is there as an implicit mental phenome- The breakdown of one’s own self in schizo-
non. It guarantees that I sense myself as the phrenic prodromes is not only a matter of self-
center of my own experiences and that I feel my perception but also of self-typification. I appre-
self as distinct from the object I am perceiving hend myself by means of typificatory schemes.
and assures that my representation of that object Self-typification is the process through which I
is experienced as distinct from the object itself. constitute my own sense of my self. This is not
When ipseity is lacking, complaints of deperson- only a process based on introspection or reflexiv-
alization and derealization arise whose cardinal ity, a private process in which I engage in an
component is a very characteristic, self-perceived idiosyncratic way. In constituting my own self
“lack of presence.” For instance, it is no longer (and my own world) I also adopt stereotyped
me the one who is perceiving that object—I am it.
204 ■ PPP / VOL. 8, NO. 2–3 / JUNE–SEPTEMBER 2001

roles (Mead 1934), which are relatively consen- disentangle themselves from hyper-identification
sual and normative identities. The person’s con- with commonsensical social roles and norms; es-
nectedness to commonsensical meanings and ste- pecially outside of clinical episodes, melancholic
reotyped roles is an essential component of the patients look hyper-normal and over-adapted (Tel-
constitution of one’s own self- and worldview. lenbach 1983; Kraus 1977, 1982), and manics,
Social psychologists have underscored that too, seem to embody a caricature of autonomy
people have two basic needs: the need to be deeply rooted in their dependence on common
similar to others and the need to be unique. sense. In short, schizophrenics are hypo-connect-
Similarity assures the validation of one’s own ed to common sense, whereas manic-depressives
identity, whereas uniqueness enhances individu- are hyper-connected to it (Stanghellini 1997).
ation. People usually meet these demands for My thesis is that the common-sense issue is
consensus and individuality by developing a self crucial for understanding psychotic (schizophrenic
that is based on socially shared categories and and manic-depressive) worlds, since the break-
based on personal constructs (optimal distinc- down of the social self, that is, the crisis of the
tiveness theory: Brewer 1991; Brewer and Pick- optimal relatedness to common sense, is one of
ett 1999). Indeed, the vulnerabilities to major the main roots of the schizophrenics’ vulnerable
psychoses can also be characterized as impair- condition and, consequently, the origin of the
ments of the dialectical movement between in- development of full-blown psychotic symptoma-
clusion-assimilation, on the one hand, and differ- tology; over-identification with common sense is
entiation-distinctiveness, on the other. the core of manic-depressive alienation. I pro-
When this balance between inclusiveness and pose that the concept of crisis of common sense
separateness breaks down, and the polarization is a very sensible index of schizophrenic vulnera-
into one of these components takes place, we bility and an effective hermeneutic tool to ac-
enter the field of psychopathology (Kretschmer count for the psychotic’s prodromal changes in
1922; Minkowski 1927; Stevens and Price 1996; self- and worldviews and pre-morbid changes in
Blankenburg 1969; Cutting 1997). The forerun- attitude towards self and world (e.g., nonconfor-
ner of this social-psychopathological approach is mity or normopathy). Persisting signs of with-
Blankenburg’s analysis of the core disorder in drawal (e.g., negative symptoms, reduced social
hebephrenic schizophrenia. Blankenburg (1969, competence, and adjustment) and productive
1971)—looking for the core of subjective phe- symptomatology (delusions and hallucinations)
nomena taking place in the intersubjective space— can be interpreted as consequences of disordered
pointed out that the fundamental character of emotional and cognitive attunement to the world.
relational deficit phenomena occurring in schizo-
phrenics is the loss of natural evidence of com- What is Common Sense? Philosophical
monsensical everyday reality. Schizophrenics, and and Psychological Cues to a
especially hebephrenics, can no longer typify their Definition of “Common Sense”
experiences along commonsense categories. For “Common sense” is not an easy concept to
them, the rootedness and at-homeness that ac- define. The eighteenth-century Italian philoso-
companies us in our everyday life are absent. pher G. B. Vico (1744) gave the following, sweep-
Persons vulnerable to schizophrenia seem to be ing definition of common sense: “It is a judg-
affected by an accentuated inclination to bracket ment without any reflection, commonly felt by a
common sense. They seem to lack and to ignore, whole order, a whole people, a whole nation or
or sometimes to refuse, commonsense categories the whole human kind.” Scottish philosopher
with which to typify their everyday experiences, and Vico’s contemporary T. Reid (1764) postu-
so that they sometimes are puzzled by ordinary lated that the human mind could harmonize with
situations and are unable to think or act accord- common sense because of an innate “instinct”;
ing to what is commonly expected. Manic-de- for Reid, common sense is a set of shared beliefs
pressives, on the other hand, seem unable to representing the rock of knowledge and truth.
STANGHELLINI / PSYCHOPATHOLOGY OF COMMON SENSE ■ 205

The construct of common sense is a coin with eryday experiences of individuals and social
two faces. On the one face, common sense is groups (Flick 1998), which has its roots in evolu-
conceptualized as a stock of knowledge-at-hand tion, and its purpose is an adaptive one, since it
useful at the level of everyday life. It is represent- provides an image of reality built up for the
ed as a set of “commonplaces,” a network of pragmatic aim of survival and adaptation (Hor-
beliefs—a background of knowledge shared by ton 1982). This adaptationist interpretation of
the members of a given culture or society, a body common sense was originally held by Locke
of rules that discipline behaviors in ordinary life (1688), who emphasized that common sense con-
situations. On the other face of the coin, com- sists of a set of empirical cause-effect relation-
mon sense is represented as a “sense” useful for ships useful for practical orientation in everyday
attuning with what is “common”; a “sense,” i.e., actions. Following Locke, many modern psy-
a psychic function aimed at understanding cur- chologists argue that the fundamental feature of
rent social situations. If we were to devise a human thinking is its need to understand the
common sense test, should we try to measure the causes of behavior and everyday events (so-called
integrity of a network of socially shared beliefs? “attribution theory”: Heider 1958). Evolution-
or the compliance to adopt the statements (the ary psychologists highlight that “our literal sur-
knots of the network) as true? or should we vival depends upon a finely tuned knowledge of
rather attempt to assess the individual capacity the causal texture of the world” (Plotkin 1997).
to pre-conceptually attune with a given social Not only the adjustment to, and survival of,
situation? each individual in his natural environment, but
I will present and discuss separately the two also the identity and integrity of a whole society
constructs: common sense as social knowledge or culture, depend on the possession of this “pri-
and common sense as attunement. mary theory” of the world called common sense.
Common sense is all that the members of a given
Common Sense as Social Knowledge society are disposed to take as obvious. How
If we look at the first face of the coin, we does this consistency in their primary theory about
conceptualize common sense as social knowl- the world originate among different members of
edge, a sort of database of constructs to typify a given group? Our knowledge of the world we
reality, which is less explicit and less defined than live in derives only in part from our personal,
scientific knowledge. In this view, common sense first-hand experience; to a much greater extent it
is also seen as a set of rules of inference shared by is socially derived. The bulk of constructs used to
a social group, through which its members con- typify others’ behaviors, courses of actions, and
ceptualize objects, situations, and other persons’ one’s own attitudes is taken for granted as a set
behaviors. It is the foundation of people’s expec- of institutionalized rules. We do not build our
tations and of meaning attributions (Moscovici common sense out of an individual inquiry into
and Hewstone 1983). As far as social situations the world—we inherit it, learning it as children
are concerned, their conceptualization is a pro- faithfully accepting the teachings of adults. We
cess of attribution of motivational explanations get acquainted with this “inherited background”
to the others’ behaviors. This process works al- at a stage of our psychological growth that is
most automatically, since motivations are attrib- antecedent to doubts and uncertainties. In short,
uted pre-reflectively, i.e., without much active we are imprinted with it.
thinking and before a conscious and deliberate The commonsense world enjoys relative sta-
search for explanation. bility and consistency among individuals belong-
In this perspective, common sense is a kind of ing to the same group, since in it, abnormalities
knowledge whose purpose is not theoretical undergo assimilation. The remarkable stability
(knowing about something), but practical (doing of common sense is due to the tendency to assim-
something) (Aristotle, Metaphysics VI, 1). Com- ilate the unusual to the usual. Abnormal (i.e.,
mon sense is the medium for organizing the ev- non-standard, non-typical, un-expected) instances
206 ■ PPP / VOL. 8, NO. 2–3 / JUNE–SEPTEMBER 2001

are as a rule assimilated to “circles of similar” or kenburg 1969, 1971; Parnas and Bovet 1991;
“normal kinds.” As a rule, experiences that fit Bovet and Parnas 1993) emphasize that common
commonsense categorizations are felt as more sense is a kind of pre-conceptual attunement
real than those that are idiosyncratic. If an expe- between the subject and the outer world which is
rience does not fit commonsense schemata, it is rooted in corporeality and affective/emotional
not the schemata that are put in jeopardy, but, life. Lack of common sense manifests itself in a
vice-versa, it is the new character of the experi- lack of the sense for the “rules of the game” of
ence that is ruled out and normalized. Wittgen- human behavior (Parnas and Bovet 1991) and in
stein (1969) argues that one’s sense of evidence the crisis of the “sense of reality” of everyday
and certainty about individual experiences does experience (Blankenburg 1971).
not derive from individual judgment, but from a There are several points of overlap between
tacit acceptance of the picture of the world inher- the phenomenological conception of common
ited from the community to which one belongs. sense and the cognitive approach described in
Two main categories of events are dealt with the previous sub-section. Both highlight the in-
by common sense—the physical and the psycho- tersubjective character of common sense (Bell
logical. Common sense represents a guideline for 1990; Smith 1995), its implications for mutual
orientation in the realms of physical objects and understanding (Schutz 1962; Searle 1995) and
events and of psychological states and situations. social adaptation, and its social origin (Schutz
Hume (1955) held that the human mind’s main 1962, 1970). However, many phenomenologists
purpose is detecting cause-effects relationships, would not agree that the main goal of common
and modern psychologists more or less confirmed sense is detecting physical causation and psycho-
his theory about the mind’s urge to establish logical motivation. The cognitivist tradition thinks
causal relations (Sperber et al. 1995). Every man that meanings are inferred from and projected
is a natural physicist and a natural psychologist onto brute facts of the world, but this is disputed
(Plotkin 1997). Guided by common sense, we by phenomenology. This is a very important point,
spontaneously look for cause-effect relationships. since to understand the difference between the
Whereas physical causation deals with the rela- cognitive approach and the phenomenological,
tionships between material objects (e.g., “If I one has to realize that for phenomenology, the
touch fire, then my hand will burn or be dam- constitution of the meaning of an object is not a
aged”), the detection of psychological motiva- derived thought (i.e., the product of an I’s think-
tion is concerned with the understanding of the ing act). A good definition of phenomenology is
others’ mental states (thoughts, feelings, inten- that this is the discipline analyzing how self and
tions, etc.) through the perception of the others’ world constitute each other as complementary
behaviors (actions, facial expressions, etc.), e.g., polarities. Understanding one’s social partners,
“If she smiles, she is happy.” Following a cogni- according to phenomenologists, does not depend
tive approach, Baron-Cohen (1995) called “mind- on a cognitive ability to detect expressions and
reading” this property of inferring mental states on a capacity to infer intentions and motivations
behind somebody’s behaviors, “mind- blindness” behind behavioral signs. The understanding of
being its pathological counterpart, evident in au- the others is not an inference of mental states,
tistic conditions. but a pre-cognitive, intuitive experience (Husserl
1977), a direct perception of the others’ emo-
Common Sense as Attunement tional life (Scheler 1973).
If we now look at the other side of the coin, Another important point of disagreement be-
common sense is represented as a kind of intui- tween the cognitive and the phenomenological
tive knowledge. Phenomenological definitions of approaches is the hypostatization of common sense
common sense, both in philosophical (Merleau- brought about by cognitive sciences. In a phe-
Ponty 1945; Husserl 1970) and in psychopatho- nomenological approach, the “attunement hy-
logical literature (Minkowski 1926, 1927; Blan- pothesis” of common sense is preferred to the
STANGHELLINI / PSYCHOPATHOLOGY OF COMMON SENSE ■ 207

“social knowledge hypothesis,” because common mann 1966). The way I apprehend the other
sense is not like an encyclopedia of socially shared contributes to the way I apprehend myself. In
behavioral rules existing somewhere in the world, this circular process, two components are in-
but mainly a process placed in face-to-face en- volved. On the one hand, I apprehend myself
counters. and the other through typificatory schemes, but
However, the concept of “attunement” is rather on the other hand, since the face-to-face situa-
vague and deserves further explications. What tion is extremely flexible and in it the other is
sort of process is referred to by “attunement,” available “through a maximum of symptoms”
and what is (or is not) a person attuned with? (Berger and Luckmann 1966), it is very difficult
The following definition can improve our un- to impose rigid patterns of typification onto the
derstanding of “common sense”: Common sense other and onto myself. In the face-to-face situa-
is what one thinks that the others think. This is a tion, the apprehension of the other and of myself
good phenomenological definition of “common may become less and less “typical” and anony-
sense,” but it needs explanations. I propose this mous and increasingly personal and original.
definition for three main reasons. It is primarily Thus I feel attuned with the phenomenal world
centered on the noetic process of attunement, when I experience it as a communal (“real”)
more than on its noematic content: how one gets world; and the phenomenal world appears as
to realize the way to behave in a certain situation such when I feel attuned with the others, that is,
and how one’s sense of reality is established, when I experience the others, like myself, as
more than what these rules of the game are and living organisms related to the world and to the
what this sense of reality consists in. It focuses others as I am related to them.
on the interaction between one individual and It is beyond the scope of this paper to deal
his social partners: a face-to-face interaction in with the nature of the self-other relation. One
which a transfer between two individuals hap- interpretation of it is the one that acknowledges
pens. It provides one possible description of the the crucial role of the lived body in the founda-
frame in which one’s knowledge about the rules tion of intersubjectivity (Merleau-Ponty 1964;
of the game of human behavior and one’s sense Dillon 1997). Intersubjectivity is based on my
of reality are established: They do not derive identification with my partner’s body that I per-
from individual judgment, but from a kind of ceive over there. I perceive his body as like my
tacit understanding of (and agreement with) one’s own. I recognize the other as an “alter ego”
partners. through an immediate perceptual linkage with
The common-sense-as-attunement paradigm his body. This is a primordial phenomenon called
assumes that the affective-conative capacity to “syncretic sociability,” antecedent to the self-
get involved in and directly perceive the other’s other distinction. Intersubjectivity is based on
mental life is the basic prerequisite for the famil- this transfer of corporeal schema (Merleau-Ponty
iarity feeling with the environment, at home, and 1964). A better word to account for the phenom-
in everyday social situations. The sense of reality enon of intersubjectivity would then be “inter-
of an experience is a product of intersubjectivity. corporeality,” since “at the most basic level, human
The “reality” of everyday life is shared with communion is a communion of flesh and not a
others: Something presents itself to me as “real” relation between isolated subjects” (Dillon 1997).
when I know that my experience corresponds to
(although is not identical with) the experience of Levels of Vulnerability
others. The definition of my own self is also a
product of intersubjectivity. The reflection about My views, in summary, concerning schizo-
myself that produces my own sense of my self is phrenic vulnerability are that it involves disor-
occasioned in the face-to-face situation by the ders of common sense, and I distinguish three
attitude toward me that the other exhibits. It is levels of vulnerability to schizophrenia (Stang-
typically a “mirror response” (Berger and Luck- hellini 2000a): 1) sensory, 2) typification, and 3)
attitudinal phenomena:
208 ■ PPP / VOL. 8, NO. 2–3 / JUNE–SEPTEMBER 2001

1. Sensory level (perception of self, body and world) ting and Murphy, deficient real-world knowl-
2. Typification level (attribution of meaning and in- edge is something different from thinking distur-
tention): bances, perceptual disorders, conversational dis-
2.1. damaged social knowledge network
course, and formal thought disorders. They argue
2.1.1. atrophy of social knowledge network
2.1.2. hypertrophy of social knowledge network that incompetent social judgment is an intrinsic
2.2. disorders of attunement feature of schizophrenia (and especially of the
3. Attitudinal level (structure of value and belief)— subgroup, hebephrenic schizophrenia) and not a
distrust towards conventional knowledge and at- consequence of environmental factors or actual
tunement: illness. The phenomenon described by Schwartz
3.1. skepticism et al. shows that dis-entanglement from common
3.2. hyper-tolerance of ambiguity
sense can occur not only through a defective
In this section, I will present a synthesis of this state (atrophy of social knowledge network) but
proposal, and in the next, focus on the attitude vice-versa via a plus condition. When all possible
of schizophrenic persons toward commonsense meanings linked to a given situation emerge,
knowledge and attunement. context-relevant meanings (Schutz 1970) are no
Sensory-level disorders (level 1) are not com- more selected from the set of all possible mean-
monsense disorders in a strict sense, but they ings. Because of a failure of the processes of
should be mentioned, because they are intercon- unburdening (Gehlen 1978) from the flooding of
nected with commonsense disorders. Sensory- perceptive stimuli, it is no longer possible to
level disorders are aberrations in self-, body-, select those meanings that are relevant to attune
and world perception. It is well established in to that given situation.
current literature that these disorders of subjec- Empirical studies assessing disorders of attun-
tive experience include sensations of loss of con- ement (level 2.2) in the phenomenological sense
trol, loss of automatism, over-stimulation; com- are currently not available. The capacity to un-
plaints of impaired world perception, of impaired derstand what is going on in another’s mind or in
expressive and receptive language, of impaired a given social situation is currently assessed in
thought, memory, and motricity; and anhedonia the form of the ability to infer the utterer’s inten-
and anxiety (Suellwold and Huber 1986). These tions behind indirect speech, or to detect a char-
disorders of basic cognition are involved in the acter’s beliefs in short stories, or to attribute
pathogenesis of schizophrenic psychoses and are mental states in non-verbal scenarios (Cocoran
related to disorders of social cognition, since et al. 1995; Frith and Cocoran 1996; Sarfati et
they interfere with the perception of external and al. 1997a,b). This approach is reliant on a cogni-
especially social reality. In the bottom-up patho- tive approach to interpersonal disorders—i.e.,
genetical hypothesis, sensory-level disorders are the theory-of-mind deficit (Frith and Frith 1988;
considered primary or basic phenomena—the Frith 1992). It is argued that schizophrenic sub-
primum movens or trouble générateur and also jects who have difficulties in extracting inten-
the conditio sine qua non of schizophrenia. tions may rely on two competing strategies of
Typification disorders (level 2) are related to decoding: They may choose the prevailing mean-
disturbances of the social knowledge network or ing of an ambiguous stimulus (e.g., a word) inde-
to a lack of attunement. Social knowledge net- pendently of the context, thus relying on their
work disorders (level 2.1) are assessed either as background knowledge (Chapman et al. 1964;
atrophies of the social knowledge database (Cut- Swiney 1984), or show facilitation for word rec-
ting and Murphy 1988, 1990) or as a kind of ognition by semantic categorization (Koh and
hypertrophy due to a hyper-extended network of Peterson 1978; Traupman 1980). In general, what
semantic associations between the concepts stored they seem to lack is a strategy to notice and
in the database itself (Spitzer 1992; Spitzer et al. extrapolate context-relevant elements and make
1993; Schwartz et al. 1997). Both disorders lead use of other systems to establish relevant connec-
to deficits in interpersonal competence. For Cut- tions, inferences, and interpretations.
STANGHELLINI / PSYCHOPATHOLOGY OF COMMON SENSE ■ 209

Attitudinal disorders (level 3) are character- On being asked whether she had started set-
ized by distrust towards common sense, i.e., con- ting herself these questions because there was
ventional knowledge and attunement. They in- some hindrance that made the so-called natural
clude a skeptical attitude towards common sense, actions of everyday life difficult for her (that is, if
a hyper-tolerance of ambiguity, and bracketing she was trying to explain life because she was not
of the unburdening process, reflecting the refusal able to live it) or independently from this, she
to conceptualize the world through the simplify- replies: “I do not know which came first, wheth-
ing views given by commonsense typificatory er my questions about life or my hindrance in
schemes and the refusal to restrict one’s appre- living. However, those questions were a hin-
hension of the world to its empirical, pragmatic, drance.” To which she adds: “I have created this
and at-hand meanings. rigid container since my childhood, perhaps be-
cause I had no exterior authoritative model. Fi-
Fighting against Heteronomia: nally something took shape that had a rigid con-
The schizophrenics’ Attitude trol function.”
toward Commonsense Knowledge During adolescence the established ideal of
and Attunement autonomy came to be added to her doubts as to
Another oft-neglected aspect of the schizo- what was natural and doubts as to her myth of
phrenic condition is the world of values of the spontaneity: “I considered everything that had to
schizophrenic person—the personal reasons for do with being with others heteronomia. What I
his or her behaviors. Psychopathologists mainly then thought to be autonomy was really autism.
emphasize sensory and typification disorders and How was I to justify my autistic way of living
overlook the schizophrenic’s reasons for actively from a theoretical point of view? By saying that
and voluntarily bracketing commonsense world- each relationship damaged me.”
views. The concept of “attitude” refers to the Her existential project is getting rid of what
individual’s philosophy of life, i.e., the structure she calls “heteronomia,” i.e., the dependence on
of values and beliefs that orients her attitudes the rules established by the others. She gets too
and actions. Persons vulnerable to schizophrenia emotionally involved when she gets in touch with
may show an attitude of distrust towards con- other people and rejects her tendency to identify
ventional knowledge and attunement. with the point of view of the others.
She now explains her choices on this subject
Ariel and the Sailors through a personal interpretation of the myth of
V.V. is a twenty-three-year-old university stu- Anphiaraus. In Greek mythology, the poet An-
phiaraus is dragged reluctantly into a war of
dent of the classics. She is cultured, sensitive, shy,
which he already knows the miserable outcome.
restless, and devoid of an ubi consistam. Ever
While he is fleeing with the Argive army, and just
since her childhood, she has felt a difference
as Periclymenus is about to stab him in the back
between what was “natural” for herself and what
was natural for others. “I was interested to know with his spear, Anphiaraus is swallowed into the
what mechanisms are involved in everyday be- ground, which was split open by a thunderbolt
from Zeus. “Before man can oppress him with
havior. How we operate in those things which
his violence and kill him, he is swept away by
we take for granted. For example: How is it that
Jupiter and made immortal. Before contact with
in the mornings we get up to have breakfast? In
reality can make him perform inauthentic ac-
order to breathe, do we need to think or not?”
She sets for herself the problem of naturalness tions, the gods gather him into their chthonic
and what is correlated with it: the ethical prob- embrace. That is how, according to the myth, his
identity is preserved.”
lem of spontaneity and authenticity. “Only spon-
Her identity and her autonomy are endan-
taneity is authentic. If I know what is right, then
gered by contact with others: “I am unable to
my action must follow spontaneously. If it does
conceive the contact and confrontation with oth-
not follow spontaneously, then (if it is performed)
it is inauthentic.” er people in any different way from heterono-
210 ■ PPP / VOL. 8, NO. 2–3 / JUNE–SEPTEMBER 2001

mia. At the moment in which someone thinks with survival, but very soon the yearning for
something about me, this thought becomes a risk autonomy becomes a flight from reality. The
for my existence, because I see others as en- Sailors stigmatize the hybris of this project in
dowed with the possibility of manipulating the which, at first, Ariel is active part, but of which it
way I am. What for other people would be no later loses control. The Sailors try to make Ariel
more than an innocent remark, for me becomes ashamed of its (the ego’s) over-ambitious project,
something that can mold me,” and she adds, “It on the one hand, and of its incapacity to live a
is very unpleasant not to be able to say ‘no.’ practical life, on the other. They underline the
When I am walking with somebody else, I do not ridiculous aspects of Ariel’s behavior, its dispro-
know if I want to turn right or left, because I portionate ambition, its excesses, and they en-
only attempt to understand what the other per- deavor to put a limit to Ariel—to normalize her
son would like to do and adapt to that. A dog behavior. Last, they accuse her behavior of “kill-
tries to understand to oblige its master, as op- ing the ego.”
posed to a cat that tries to understand so as to do A merciless struggle takes place between Ariel
as it likes.” The presence of another person sus- and the Sailors. The ego’s space becomes restrict-
pends her ability to make autonomous choices: ed under the pressure of Ariel’s overwhelming
“To understand and to comply are not two sepa- yearning for autonomy and the sarcastic com-
rate things for me.” She explains that the prob- ments of the Sailors that fan the flames of Ariel’s
lem arises from the lability of her boundaries: hybris. Finally, the ego dies. From this moment
“To have an experience means to gamble with on, “the use of the personal pronoun ‘I’ becomes
my boundaries. For me contacts with everything a mere linguistic artifice, a simple concession to
are particularly strong and involving. I am un- communication.” Where before the ego used to
able to mediate. And if I speak with living beings be, now, “somewhere in the middle there is just a
it is even worse.” sort of puppet,” whose strings are pulled some-
As the years go by, her identity splits into two times by Ariel and sometimes by the Sailors.
opposite halves: ethereal Ariel, the eternal child At first, the Sailors “are just a metaphor”: a
who plays and lives within the all-powerful mag- metaphor of common sense. “I can say that the
ic of thought divided from reality, and Sailors, a ‘Sailors’ are everything that questions authentic-
sort of Greek tragedy chorus, critical and mock- ity and spontaneity, and whatever obliges me to
ing, that stigmatizes Ariel’s hybris. Ariel was live everyday life.” Up until secondary school
born in secondary school days, at first just as times, the Sailors used to represent a counter-
“the child” who strove to live the present mo- point with which to argue, but matters have
ment. Ariel is the yearning for autonomy as an changed since late adolescence and up until the
absolute value, reached through play and pure present day. With the ego’s death, which took
thought. Everyday reality is painful because it is place in those years, the Sailors have come to be
too close (“The contact with everything is partic- Ariel’s only check and so come to be something
ularly strong”), but it is problematic also be- concrete—they become substance: “Until I was
cause it is at an unreachable distance: “Everyday at secondary school, they had no correspondence
reality is not to be despised. The problem is that with the exterior that could confirm what they
it is distant. And the solution is to get even said. Now there are entities that I call Sailors.
further away.” Gradually, but relentlessly, Ariel Before, they were moments. We talked; they talked
proceeds to the “euthanasia of the ego.” First, it to me. Now they do not talk to me; they speak.
restricts it in space, in the name of its own all- First, they were part of me, now no longer.” The
powerful ambition of autonomy; finally, it con- Sailors become hallucinatory voices.
tributes to its end. The ego’s incipient death and The Sailors “lead Ariel to take advantage of
Ariel’s overbearing power find an immediate con- supposed signs to discover what other people
sequence in the advent of the Sailors. At first think.” The Sailors’ aim is to bring Ariel back
Ariel’s ambitions might have been compatible inside a shareable horizon of meaning. They are
STANGHELLINI / PSYCHOPATHOLOGY OF COMMON SENSE ■ 211

also a guide to interpret other people’s behavior M.M. is a forty-two-year-old woman affected
and thoughts: “The interpretation of other peo- by paranoid schizophrenia. During a therapy ses-
ple’s thoughts always starts from what the Sail- sion, she asked me and herself, “What is ‘reason-
ors think.” The Sailors’ function is to lead Ariel ableness?’ It is the light that allows the interpre-
back to the realm of common sense; but in so tation of reality. In me it is switched off. It is not
doing, they frustrate the yearning for autonomy. spontaneous. One must work on it. I feel switched
For instance, during an oral test at university, the off here in my forehead. Interpreting reality is
Sailors lay down the rules of the game for a also saying, ‘I don’t like him!’ It is a subjective
standard university exam, preventing the student interpretation of reality. Everything becomes gray,
from personalizing the situation, from express- flat. Anything goes. Indeed, nothing goes: I can-
ing herself in an autonomous and original man- not move away from my bed. I do feel a ‘lunar’
ner. The Sailors impose their own lines, which energy that is tackling the sun and eclipses it. I
are lines that follow the rules, that say, “This is experience the others as if they were empty. The
the way to behave,” which is an anonymous and sun is missing. The perception of oneness and
impersonal behavior—that aurea mediocritas, multiplicity is missing. When a subject gets to
which is so disliked by Ariel. At the height of the know something, he becomes one with it. But
piercing hallucinatory din, they overthrow Ariel: subjectivity is needed in order to get to know
“The Sailors have exaggerated. In their efforts to something. In me, it is as if subjectivity were
control Ariel, they have chased it away altogether.” subjugated, and I do not know by what. I dive a
lot of times into my psychologist’s head, because
Case Reports I can manage to get out from it. I do not dive into
P.S. is a forty-two-year-old man who has been my mother’s head because I am scared. She was a
affected by paranoid schizophrenia since the age medium. I am afraid to get lost in her head, to get
of twenty. At the onset of his psychosis, he was caught in it.”
trying in various ways to compensate for his
difficulties in getting in touch with other people. Case Vignettes
He had no secure ground to interpret the others’ E.C., a young schizophrenic, speaks out his
intentions. He lacked the structure of the rules of disdainful refusal of conventional values and be-
social life and systematically set about searching liefs that he identifies with his parents’ teachings.
for a well-grounded and natural style of behav- M.Mo., another young schizophrenic man,
ior. For instance, he was busy with an ethological when recovered from an acute schizo- obsessive
study of the “biological” (i.e., not “cultural,” episode, says that what he hates most is “to be
not artificial) foundation of the others’ behaviors persuaded by the others” and, therefore, he avoids
through a double observation of animal and hu- any discussion.
man habits. The former was done through TV T.T.R, another schizotype, tells that his reason
documentaries, the latter via the analyses of hu- for withdrawal is that he hates the inauthenticity
man interactions in public parks. An atrophy in of the others and any standard and taken-for-
his knowledge of the “rules of the game” led him granted view about the world. He does not want
to engage in intellectual investigations and to “to get caught in their way of thinking.”
establish his own “know-how” for social inter- G. B., a thirty-nine-year-old schizoid, who
actions in a reflective way. Many years after the withdrew into his house about ten years ago and
onset of his psychosis, he would explain that his spends much of his time sitting on his bed in a
withdrawal was also a consequence of his dis- very unnatural position, is afraid of starting a
dain for the others’ opinions, but mainly the program of body awareness and rehabilitation,
effect of his fright to lose his own ideas in the because this is his “personal, unique posture,”
face-to-face interactions with the others. He iron- comfortable for him, although not spontaneous,
ically says, “I feel weak, very weak . . . someone and above all, different from the posture of all
would say sensible.” the others.
212 ■ PPP / VOL. 8, NO. 2–3 / JUNE–SEPTEMBER 2001

These persons’ experiences reflect disorders of a shift to the left along the “intelligence-intu-
the phenomenal self and, in particular, a lack of ition” axis. This issue is also addressed by
ipseity, e.g., patients V.V. and M.Ma. get too Minkowski’s (1927) “morbid rationalism” and
emotionally involved when they get in touch Sass’s (1992) “hyper-reflexivity.” While the lat-
with other people. ter especially addresses the topic of the schizo-
However, these people’s reports especially re- phrenic mind’s self-destruction, Minkowski usu-
flect disorders of the social self, i.e., the loss of ally holds that morbid rationalism is a coping
common sense (e.g., V.V. and P.S.). Often, their reaction that invades the psychic life of the indi-
conduct shows the deliberate attempt to disen- vidual when she has lost the vital contact with
gage from all the sources of taken-for-granted- reality. Morbid rationalism is an attempt to rees-
ness, unwitting typification and inauthenticity tablish new rules for typification when life can-
(e.g., V.V and E.C.). not be lived anymore, but only thought
Since many of them suffer from an over-recep- (Minkowski 1947). Loss of the vital contact with
tiveness of the thoughts of the others (e.g., P.S., reality and of common sense, on the one hand,
V.V., M.Ma.), their existential project is getting and fear of inclusion and need for differentia-
rid of what V.V. calls “heteronomia,” i.e., the tion, on the other, are two faces of the same coin.
dependence on the rules established by the others. It can neither be established, once and for all,
These people’s experiences may spring from which is the primary and which the secondary
their proneness to heteronomia but also from set of phenomena in a pathogenetical sense, nor
their fear of an excess of attunement and adapta- which of the two is the sole fundamental condi-
tion (e.g., V.V.). Their behaviors may reflect their tion of possibility of schizophrenic psychoses in
tragic fight for differentiation and uniqueness an anthropological sense.
(e.g., G.B.) and their need for distinctiveness and Schizophrenic vulnerability is often consid-
individuation (e.g., P.S., M.Mo., T.T.R.). Since ered as a condition characterized by defective
for them fear of assimilation and an urge for attunement to the social environment. Yet, the
differentiation are more important than related- schizophrenic’s skeptical behaviors may reflect
ness, the price they all pay for individuation is the attempt to disengage from heteronomia, i.e.,
being disconnected from spontaneity, instinctive- over-receptiveness of the thoughts of others (rath-
ness, automatic actions, and above all, intercor- er than the lack of socially shared roles and rules
poreality and intersubjectivity. for engaging in “real life” or a purely theoretical
refusal of conventionality). It is common to find
The Schizophrenic’s Skeptical among persons vulnerable to schizophrenia and
Attitude towards Common Sense young schizophrenics the rejection of attunement
Young schizophrenics often show a skeptical and intuitiveness, because these are considered
attitude towards conventional typifications, a dis- sources of conformity, inauthenticity, narrow-
trust of pre-reflective attunement, and an em- mindedness, loss of selfness, and of differentia-
phasis on rationality and abstract thinking. When tion. We might call this individualistic attitude
this happens, the destruction of the building antagonomia, because it is based on the opposi-
blocks of everyday experience seems to come tion to the others’ norms, which are experienced
from above and not from the bottom: It is by as one dangerous source of loss of individuality.
means of a philosophical (or pseudo-philosophi-
cal) skepticism that common sense is dismissed. The Schizophrenic’s Hyper-Tolerance
The German philosopher Rosenzweig (1984) of Ambiguity
ironically defined this paralysis of commonsense Another pathway to the loss of common sense
“apoplexia philosophica,” an intellectualistic con- can originate from a hyper-tolerance of ambigu-
dition derived from a distrust of commonsense ity. Tolerance of ambiguity is the ease with which
typification and related to hyper-reflexivity. Cut- a person can perceive dissonant characteristics in
ting (1997) described this condition as related to the same object, person, or situation (Frenkel-
STANGHELLINI / PSYCHOPATHOLOGY OF COMMON SENSE ■ 213

Brunswik 1949). This phenomenon was first stud- The philosophical paragon of this attitude,
ied in the so-called “authoritarian personality” which may predispose to schizophrenic experi-
(Adorno et al. 1950), the anthropological config- ences, is the “art of memory” (Yates 1966; Rossi
uration that predisposes individuals to be preju- 1983), i.e., a mental exercise to improve memory
diced. However, the tendency to rule out ambi- through the activation of fluid semantic associa-
guities and uncertainties from one’s own tions. The art of memory, however, is not only a
life-world is very common. The process through means to enhance memory, but also an esoteric
which the complexity of reality is simplified and hermeneutic instrument to break through the
only one of the multiplicity of possible meanings innermost secrets of Nature.
of a given situation becomes fixated was called Suspending commonsense worldview, brack-
by Gehlen (1978) the “unburdening process” eting the unburdening process, enlarging one’s
(Entlastung). Gehlen thought that this symbolic own capacity to be impressed by different mean-
process was the structural law of human action, ings, looking for a metaphysical dimension of
since through it, only those stimuli and meanings reality, and disengaging from intersubjectivity
are selected that are relevant for a given action. are the many facets of the same phenomenon.
Among the main features of the vulnerability They form a Gestalt in which affective-conative
to schizophrenia, over-inclusive thinking (Cam- (i.e., lack of attunement), cognitive (i.e., over-
eron 1944) is one of the best established—mean- inclusive thinking), and attitudinal phenomena
ings that are remotely linked to each other be- (i.e., concern for the complexity of reality and
come incorporated within the same train of for the uniqueness of one’s own worldview) are
thoughts. As in the case of skepticism, the schizo- related coherently to each other.
phrenics’ hyper-tolerance of ambiguity, rather
than a disorder of thinking, may also be a delib- Conclusions
erate epistemological attitude, i.e., the concern
for the complexity of reality and the rejection of In this paper, which builds on and extends
taken-for-granted simplifications. Facts-in-the-world contributions of the phenomenological tradition,
cannot be caught by a single conceptualization, I have attempted to sketch a theoretical frame-
reducing their multifaceted complexity to a uni- work for exploring some fundamental features
dimensional surface designation. If one conceives of schizophrenic vulnerability. The basic hypoth-
of the world as a “forest of symbols” and each esis is that the interpersonal disorder observed in
symbol as a bundle of facets, only a webwork of schizophrenic patients is not a consequence of
concepts can catch its essence via a flow of ad- acute symptomatology, or a social or institution-
umbrations showing its infinite, changing profiles. al artifact, but a fundamental aspect of the vul-
The bracketing of the unburdening process nerability to schizophrenic breakdown. Psycho-
and the attitude of intolerance towards the re- pathological studies, and mainly phenomenological
stricted horizon of common sense can be traced analyses, have attempted to describe and define
back to the individual’s set of values and beliefs, this basic interpersonal disorder, one compre-
as it is reflected in the case of the E.B., a young hensive definition being “lack of common sense.”
schizophrenic who does all he can to enhance his Traditional phenomenological analyses of
memory and the understanding capacity of his schizophrenic vulnerability and of the disorders
mind. He puts forward all his strength to volun- occurring in early schizophrenia emphasize the
tarily connect the perception of the meaning of importance of lack of ipseity and hyper- reflexiv-
one object with a network of associated mean- ity. It is commonly argued that the lack of the
ings. In this case, an enlarged horizon of mean- feeling of distinctiveness between one’s own self
ings does not simply reflect a forceful train of and the outer world (lack of ipseity), and the
more or less relevant associations, but reveals a heightened engagement in monitoring oneself in-
deliberate attempt to enlarge one’s own mental volving the spatialization of one’s own bodily
capacities to transcend the commonsense world. and mental phenomena (hyper-reflexivity), can
214 ■ PPP / VOL. 8, NO. 2–3 / JUNE–SEPTEMBER 2001

entail interpersonal disorders. However, these Although empirical studies on the interper-
analyses of the phenomenal self in early schizo- sonal disturbances in schizophrenia, which are
phrenia catch only one dimension of schizophren- mainly based on cognitive models, demonstrate
ic vulnerability (i.e., the dimension of the person- that these disturbances can be assessed as senso-
al self), disregarding the fact that the self is not a ry-level disorders (level 1) and as disorders of the
purely personal but, rather, a social phenome- social knowledge network (level 2.1), I have also
non. In this paper, I maintained that our exist- argued that there are two other kinds of psycho-
ence is fundamentally tied to a social existence pathological phenomena to be taken into ac-
and that one’s sense of presence derives from the count: disorders of attunement (level 2.2) and
way one constitutes oneself and the world in the personal attitude toward commonsense
social situations. The sense of “reality” of an knowledge and attunement (level 3). To establish
experience and the definition of one’s own self a comprehensive understanding of the interper-
are products of intersubjectivity; hence, I argued sonal disorders occurring in schizophrenia, one
that disorders of intersubjectivity can entail dis- should not overlook the concepts of “lack of
orders of the personal self. Therefore, the need intuitive attunement” and of “antagonomia.”
emerges for integrating traditional phenomeno- The affective-conative capacity for attunement
logical views on phenomenal self disorders in is the basic prerequisite for getting involved in
early schizophrenia with the analyses of the so- and directly perceiving the other’s mental life
cial self of schizotypes and young schizophrenics and for feeling familiarly related to the social
in the light of disorders of common sense. environment. When intuitive attunement is dis-
To stipulate a satisfactory definition of “com- ordered, not only do the others appear enigmatic
mon sense,” I have gathered philosophical cues and the social environment uncanny, but also,
and empirical psychopathological evidence. Com- one’s sense of the self and the boundaries be-
mon sense can be represented as a network of tween oneself and the others may become blurred.
beliefs (i.e., social knowledge) and as a basic Antagonomia is the core phenomenon of the
individual attunement with the social world of schizophrenic’s vulnerable system of values and
an intuitive kind. Whereas the concept of “social beliefs. It is characterized by the distrust towards
knowledge” defines the background of constructs conventional knowledge and attunement, which
useful for organizing the everyday experiences, includes skepticism towards common sense and
the concept of “attunement” reflects the affec- hyper-tolerance of ambiguity, reflecting the re-
tive-conative capacity to get involved in the oth- fusal to conceptualize the world through the sim-
ers’ lives and to catch context-relevant cues to plifying views given by common sense. Since
make sense of the others and of situations. I have conventional knowledge is experienced as a dan-
tried to point out the main differences between gerous source of loss of individuality, their rejec-
these two—cognitive and phenomenological— tion manifests itself as the deliberate attempt to
theoretical approaches and the reasons why the disconnect oneself from the others in which con-
second should not be overlooked and is probably ventionality is embodied.
to be preferred: The understanding of the others In the schizophrenic world, disorders of ipse-
is not an inference of mental states, but a pre- ity (phenomenal self disorders), disorders of at-
cognitive, intuitive experience, a direct percep- tunement (affective-conative disorders), and an-
tion of the others’ emotional life. The fundamen- tagonomia (attitudinal disorders) are related
tal sphere on which intersubjectivity is built can coherently to each other and form a Gestalt.
be understood better as a process placed in face- However, the causal relationships between these
to-face encounters and based in intercorporeali- different phenomena need further empirical in-
ty—my identification with my partner’s body vestigations. In addition, the relationship between
that I perceive over there—rather than as an the disorders of attunement and antagonomia
encyclopedia of socially shared behavioral rules and the disturbances of “social knowledge” needs
existing somewhere in the world. to be empirically examined in more detail. It
STANGHELLINI / PSYCHOPATHOLOGY OF COMMON SENSE ■ 215

could be argued that lack of social knowledge from intersubjectivity, intercorporeality, and tak-
and lack of attunement are the two faces of the en-for-grantedness—is the price some pay for
same psychopathological condition, but it could our tragic fight for individuation. Schizophrenic
also be hypothesized that the deficit in social vulnerability, in this sense, is an anomalous phi-
knowledge is an epiphenomenon of the lack of losophy of life. “What I then thought to be au-
attunement, the latter responsible for a deficient tonomy was really autism,” are the words of a
development in one’s life course of the knowl- twenty-three-year-old patient who, since her ad-
edge of everyday social issues. Furthermore, a olescence, had been embroiled in a self-destruc-
disorder of corporeality, e.g., of the perception tive Odyssey to overcome heteronomia, and I
of one’s own bodily sensations, may be involved take her words as puzzling evidence of our so-
in the pathogenesis of defective attunement (i.e., cial, that is, vulnerable descent.
inter-corporeality) and of a deficit in social func-
tioning. Moreover, a disorder of social knowl- References
edge could be an epiphenomenon of antagonomia. APA. 1994. Diagnostic and statistical manual of men-
These investigations can improve the clinical- tal disorders, 4th ed. (DSM-IV). Washington DC:
phenomenological assessment and characteriza- APA.
tion of single cases and allow the definition of Aristotle. 1953. Metaphysics. In Aristotelis opera.
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
subcategories within the schizophrenic spectrum,
Baron-Cohen, S. 1995. Mindblindness: An essay on
according to specific areas of interpersonal disor- autism and theory of mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.
ders. Many researchers have stigmatized the clin- Bell, D. 1990. Husserl. London and New York: Rout-
ical heterogeneity of the “group of schizophre- ledge.
nias”: The subcategorization of the schizophrenic Berger, P. L., and T. Luckmann. 1996. The social
spectrum, in terms of different components of construction of reality. A treatise in the sociology
the interpersonal disorder, could provide a more of knowledge. New York: Anchor Books.
Blankenburg, W. 1969. Ansaetze zu einer Psycho-
reliable basis for epidemiological (high-risk stud-
pathologie des “common sense”. Confinia Psychi-
ies) and neuro-biological (structural and func- atry 12:144–63.
tional correlates) research. ———. 1971. Der Verlust der natuerlichen Selbstver-
In practical terms, the assessment of the indi- taendlichkeit. Ein Beitrag zur Psychopathologie
vidual’s attitude is fundamental in promoting a Symptomarmer Schizophrenien. Stuttgart: Enke.
therapeutic alliance to empathize with her symp- Bleuler, E. 1922. Die Probleme der Schizoidie und der
toms and also to understand her life-projects. Syntonie. Zeitschrift fuer die Gesamte Neurologie
Persons affected by early manifestations of psy- und Psychiatrie 78:373–99.
Bovet, P., and J. Parnas. 1993. Schizophrenic delu-
choses may not be aware of their vulnerability
sions: A phenomenological approach. Schizophre-
and, therefore, drop out of preventive programs. nia Bulletin 19(3):579–97.
Alternative effective therapeutic projects can be Brewer, M. B. 1991. The social self: On being the
based on the understanding of the system of same and different at the same time. Personality
values and beliefs of the person and on cooperat- and Social Psychology Bulletin 17:475–82.
ing with him/her in evaluating the pros and cons Brewer, M. B., and C. L. Pickett. 1999. Distinctive-
of his/her philosophy of life. ness motives as a source of the social self. In The
psychology of the social self, ed. T. R. Tyler, R. M.
In terms of an anthropological-philosophical
Kramer, and O. P. John. Mahwah and London:
viewpoint, schizophrenic vulnerability represents Lawrence Erlbaum.
miscarried attempts to drastically solve the Self- Broks, P. 1997. Brain, self, and others: The neuropsy-
Other existential dilemma. The vulnerabilities to chology of social cognition. In Schizotypy. Impli-
major psychoses can be characterized as impair- cation for illness and health, ed. G. Claridge. Ox-
ments of the dialectical movement between the ford: Oxford University Press.
need for assimilation-consensus, on the one hand, Brothers, L. A. 1992. Perception of social acts in
and distinctiveness- individuation, on the other. primates cognition and neurobiology. Seminars in
Neurosciences 4:409–14.
Being disconnected from common sense—i.e.,
216 ■ PPP / VOL. 8, NO. 2–3 / JUNE–SEPTEMBER 2001

Chapman, J. 1966. The early symptoms of schizo- Henry, M. 2000. Incarnation. Une Philosophie de la
phrenia. British Journal of Psychiatry 121:225–63. Chair. Paris: Sevil.
Chapman, L. J., J. P. Chapman, and G. A. Miller. Hodges, A., M. Byrne, E. Grant et al. 1999. People at
1964. A theory of verbal behaviour in schizophre- risk of schizophrenia. Sample characteristics of the
nia. In Progress in experimental personality re- first 100 cases in the Edinburgh high-risk study.
search, ed. B. A. Maher. New York: Academic British Journal of Psychiatry 174:547–553.
Press. Horton, R. 1982. Tradition and modernity revisited.
Conrad, J. 1966. Die beginnende Schizophrenie. Stut- In Rationality and relativism, ed. M. Hollis and S.
tgart: Thieme. Lukes. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Cocoran, R., G. Mercer, and C. D. Frith. 1995. Schizo- Huber, G. 1966. Reine Defektsyndrome und Basissta-
phrenia, symptomatology and social inference: In- dien endogener Psychosen. Fortschritte fuer Neu-
vestigating the ‘theory of mind’ in people with rologie und Psychiatrie 34:409–26.
schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Research 17:5–13. Hume, D. A 1955. Treatise of human nature, London
Cutting, J. 1997. Principles of psychopathology. Two 1739–40. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
worlds-two minds-two hemispheres. Oxford: Ox- Husserl, E. 1970. The crisis of the European sciences
ford University Press. and transcendental phenomenology: An introduc-
Cutting, J., and D. Murphy. 1988. Schizophrenic thought tion to phenomenological philosophy. Evanston:
disorder. A psychological and organic interpreta- Northwestern University Press (Husserliana VII).
tion. British Journal of Psychiatry 152:310–19. ———. 1977. Cartesians meditations: An introduc-
———. 1990. Impaired ability of schizophrenics, rel- tion to phenomenology. The Hague: Nijhoff (Hus-
ative to manics or depressives, to appreciate social serliana I).
knowledge about their culture. British Journal of Janzarik, W. 1959. Dynamische Grundkonstellation-
Psychiatry 157:355–58. en in endogenen Psychosen. Berlin: Springer.
Dillon, M. C. 1997. Merleau-Ponty’s ontology. Evan- Jaspers, K. 1997. General psychopathology. Baltimore
ston: Northwestern University Press. and London: The Johns Hopkins University Press.
Dworkin, R. H., B. A. Cornblatt, R. Friedman et al. Klosterkoetter, J. 1988. Basissymptome un End-
1993. Childhood precursors of affective vs. social phaenomene der Schizophrenie. Berlin: Springer.
deficits in adolescents at risk of schizophrenia. Koh, S. D., and R. A. Peterson. 1978. Encoding orien-
Schizophrenia Bulletin 19:563–77. tation and the remembering of schizophrenic young
Dworkin, R. H., L. A. Lewis, B. A. Cornblatt et al. adults. Journal of Abnormal Psychology 87:303–
1994. Social competence deficits in adolescents at 13.
risk of schizophrenia. Journal of Nervous and Men- Kraus, A. 1977. Sozialverhalten und Psychosen Ma-
tal Disease 182:103–108. nisch-Depressiver. Stuttgart: Enke.
Flick, U. 1998. Everyday knowledge in social psychol- ———. 1982. Identity and psychosis of the manic-
ogy. In The psychology of the social, ed. U. Flick. depressive. In Phenomenology and psychiatry, ed.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. A. J. J. De Koning and F. A. Jenner. London: Aca-
Frenkel-Brunswik, E. 1949. Intolerance of ambiguity demic Press.
as an emotional and perceptual personality vari- Kretschmer, E. 1922. Koerperbau und Charakter. Ber-
able. Journal of Personality 18:108–43. lin-Goettingen-Heidelberg: Springer.
Frith, C. D. 1992. The cognitive neuropsychology of Lieberman, P. B. 1989. “Objective” methods and “sub-
schizophrenia. Hove: Lawrence Erlbaum. jective” experiences. Schizophrenia Bulletin
Frith, C. D, and U. Frith. 1988. Elective affinities in 15(2):267–75.
schizophrenia and childhood autism. In Social psy- Locke, J. 1688. An essay concerning human under-
chiatry: Theory, methodology and practice, ed. P. standing, ed. A. C. Frazer. Oxford (1894).
Bebbington. New Brunswick: Transactions. Maj, M. 1998. Critique of the DSM-IV operational
Frith, C. D., and R. Cocoran. 1996. Exploring ‘theory diagnostic criteria for schizophrenia. British Jour-
of mind’ in people with schizophrenia. Psychologi- nal of Psychiatry 172:458–60.
cal Medicine 26:521–30. Malmberg, A., G. Lewis, A. David et al. 1998. Pre-
Gehlen, A. 1978. Der Mensch. Seine Natur und seine morbid adjustment and personality in people with
Stellung in der Welt. Wiesbaden: Akademische Ve- schizophrenia. British Journal of Psychiatry
lagsgesellschaft Athenaion. 172:308–13.
Harré, R. 1998. The singular self. London/Thousand Mead, G. H. 1934. Mind, self, and society. Chicago:
Oaks/New Delhi: SAGE Publications. Chicago University Press.
Heider, F. 1958. The psychology of interpersonal rela- Merleau-Ponty, M. 1945. Phénomenologie de la per-
tions. New York: Wiley. ception. Paris: Gallimard.
STANGHELLINI / PSYCHOPATHOLOGY OF COMMON SENSE ■ 217

———. 1964. Les Relations avec autrui chez l’enfant Sass, L. A. 1992. Madness and modernism. Insanity
[The child’s relations with others]. In The primacy in the light of modern art, literature, and thought.
of perception. Evanston: Northwestern University Cambridge and London: Harvard University Press.
Press. Scheler, M. 1973. Wesen und Formen der Sympathie.
Minkowski, E. 1926. La notion de perte de contact Bern: Franke.
vital avec la réalité et ses applications en psycho- Schutz, A. 1962. Common sense and scientific inter-
pathologie. Paris: Jouve & Cie. pretation of human action. In Collected papers, I.
———. 1927. La schizophrénie. Psychopathologie des The problem of social reality. The Hague: Nijhoff.
schizoides et des schizophrènes (2d ed. 1953). Par- ———. 1970. Reflections on the problem of rele-
is: Payot. vance. New York and London: Yale University
———. 1947. Psychiatrie et métaphysique (A la re- Press.
cherche de l’humain et du vecu). Revue de Méta- Schwartz, M. A., O. P. Wiggins, and M. Spitzer. 1997.
physique et de Morale 52:3–4, 33–358. Psychotic experience and disordered thinking: A
Moscovici, S., and M. Hewstone. 1983. Social repre- reappraisal from new perspectives. Journal of Ner-
sentations and social explanations: From the ‘na- vous and Mental Disease 185, 3:176–87.
ive’ to the ‘amateur’ scientist. In Attribution theo- Searle, J. R. 1995. The construction of social reality.
ry: Social and functional extensions, ed. M. New York: Free Press.
Hewstone. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Smith, B. 1995. Common sense. In The Cambridge
Parnas, J., and A. Jorgensen. 1989. Pre-morbid psy- companion to Husserl, ed. B. Smith and D. Woo-
chopathology in schizophrenia spectrum. British druff Smith. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Journal of Psychiatry 155:623–27. Press.
Parnas, J., and P. Bovet. 1991. Autism in schizophre- Sperber, D., D. Premack, and A. J. Premack ed. 1995.
nia revisited. Comprehensive Psychiatry 32:7, 21. Causal cognition. Oxford: The Clarendon Press.
Parnas, J., F. Schlusinger, H. Schlusinger et al. 1982. Spitzer, M. 1992. Word associations in experimental
Behavioral precursors of schizophrenia spectrum. psychopathology: A historical perspective. In Phe-
Archives of General Psychiatry 39:658–64. nomenology, language, and schizophrenia, ed. M.
Parnas, J., Jansson L., Sass L.A., and Handest P. 1998. Spitzer, Ch. Mundt, M. A. Schwartz, and F. Ue-
Self-experience in the prodromal phases of schizo- hlein. New York: Springer.
phrenia: A pilot study of first-admissions. Neurol- Spitzer, M., U. Braun, L. Hermle et al. 1993. Associa-
ogy, Psychiatry and Brain Research 6:97–106. tive semantic network dysfunctions in thought-
Penn, D. L., W. Corrigan, R. P. Bentall R.P. et al. disordered schizophrenic patients: Direct evidence
1997. Social cognition and schizophrenia. Psycho- from indirect semantic priming. Biological Psychi-
logical Bulletin 121:114–32. atry 34:864–77.
Plotkin, H. 1997. Evolution in mind. London: Pen- Stanghellini, G. 1997. For an anthropology of vulner-
guin. ability. Psychopathology 30:1–11.
Reid, T. 1764. An inquiry into the human mind, on ———. 2000a. Vulnerability to schizophrenia and
the principles of common sense. Edinburgh, Scot- lack of common sense. Schizophrenia Bulletin 26(4):
land: Edinburgh University Press, 1997. 775–87.
Resch, F. 1992. Therapie der Adoleszentenpsychosen. ———. 2000b. Phenomenology of the social self of
Stuttgart: Thieme-Copytech. the melancholic type and of the schizotype. In
Rosenzweig, F. 1984. Das Buechlein vom gesunden Exploring the self, ed. D. Zahavi. Amsterdam:
und kranken Menschverstand. Athenaeum: Juedis- John Benjamins.
cher Verlag. Stevens, A., and J. Price. 1996. Evolutionary psychia-
Rossi, P. 1983. Clavis universalis. Arti della memoria try. A new beginning. London and New York:
e logica combinatoria da Lullo a Leibniz. Bologna: Routledge.
Il Mulino. Strawson, G. 1999. The self. In Models of the self, ed.
Sarfati, Y., M. C. Hardy-Bailé, J. Nadel et al. 1997a. S. Gallagher and J. Shear. Thorverton: Imprint
Attribution of mental states to others by schizo- Academic.
phrenic patients. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry 2,1:1– Suellwold, L., and G. Huber. 1986. Schizophrene Ba-
17. sisstoerungen. Berlin: Springer.
Sarfati, Y., M. C. Hardy-Bailé, C. Besch. et al. 1997b. Swiney, D. A. 1984. Theoretical and methodological
Attributions of intentions to others in people with issues in cognitive science: A psycholinguistic per-
schizophrenia: A non-verbal exploration with comic spective. In Methods and tactics in cognitive sci-
strips. Schizophrenia Research 25:199–209. ence, ed. W. Kintsch, J. R. Miller, and P. G. Polt-
son. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum.
218 ■ PPP / VOL. 8, NO. 2–3 / JUNE–SEPTEMBER 2001

Tellenbach, H. 1983. Melancholie. Problemgeschich- Vico, G. B. 1744. Scienza Nuova.


te, Endogenitaet, Typologie, Pathogenese, Klinik, Wittgenstein, L. 1969. On certainty. Oxford: Basil
3d ed. Berlin: Springer. Blackwell.
Traupman, K. L. 1980. Encoding process memory for Yates, F. A. 1966. The art of memory. London: Rout-
categorically related words by schizophrenic pa- ledge and Kegan Paul.
tients. Journal of Abnormal Psychology 89:704–
13.

Вам также может понравиться