Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 67

Aquinas Lecture 1947, P^U

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY AND PHILOSOPHICAL

EDUCATION
Under
the Auspices of the Aristotelian Society

of Marquette University

BY
fiTIENNE GILSON
of
the

Academie

frangaise,

Professor

of

the

History of Mediaeval Philosophy, Pontifical


Institute of

Mediaeval Studies, Toronto.

MARQUETTE UNIVERSITY MILWAUKEE


1948

PRESS

Gerard Smith,

S.J.,

censor deputatus

Milwaukiae, die 24 Decembris, 1947

imprimatur
IjlMoyses E. Kiley

Archiepiscopus Milwaukiensis

Milwaukiae, die

mensis Januarii, 1948

COPYRIGHT 1948
BY THE ARISTOTELIAN SOCIETY OF MARQUETTE UNIVERSITY

To
A. C. Pegis

Who Knows Why

PREFATORY
The
Aristotelian Society of Marquette

University each year invites a scholar to deliver

a lecture in honor of

St.

Thomas

Aquinas. Customarily delivered on the Sun-

day nearest March


Society's

7th, the feast

day of the
are

patron

saint,

these

lectures

called the

Aquinas

lectures.

In 1947, after Dr.


livered
a
lecture,

Vernon Bourke

de-

"St.

Thomas and
whose
duties

the

Greek Moralists," on March 9 the Society


invited another scholar,

do

not permit him to come to the University

on the customary

date,

to

give another
It

Aquinas lecture in the

fall.

now

has the

pleasure of recording that lecture, given


Oct. 26, by Etienne Gilson of the Fran^aise.

Academie

Etienne Henri
13,

Gilson was

bom

June

1884

at Paris.

He

received his Agrege in

1907 and became Docteur-es-Lettres in 1913.

At

the Sorbonne he

was

a pupil of Lucien

Levy-Bruhi

who

taught him historical meth-

od and suggested the study of Descartes'


borrowings

from Scholasticism,
to St.

work

which led him

Thomas Aquinas and

the middle ages, the principal concern of


his scholarly career.
at the

He was

also a pupil,

College de France, of Henri Bergson,


lectures" he recently said "still re-

"whose main
in

my memory

as so

many hours
and

of

intellectual transfiguration,"
calls

whom

he

"the only living master in philosophy"

he ever had.
In 1913 he taught at the University of
Lille.

During the

first

world war he was a


in

machine-gunnery

captain

the

French

army, was captured at Verdun and spent


his time in a

German

prisoner of war

camp

writing and studying. After the war, in

1919, he joined the faculty of the University

of Strasbourg.

In 1921 he returned to

the Sorbonne, this time to teach,

and

re-

mained there

until 1932

when he was

elect-

ed to the College de France.

He

is

now

Pro-

fessor of the Philosophy of the


at the

Middle Ages

College de France. In 1929 he also

became Director of Studies and Professor


of the History of Mediaeval Philosophy at
the newly established Institute of Mediaeval Studies, Toronto, Canada, of
is

which he
1939 was

a co-founder

and which

in

raised to a Pontifical Institute by Pius XII.

He

continues in those positions now. Ordi-

narily,

he teaches in Toronto during the


to Paris at Christmas time.

fall

and returns

Professor Gilson has held notable


tureships. In 1930

lec-

and 1931 he gave the

Gifford Lectures at the University of Aberdeen, Scotland; in 1936-37 he gave the Wil-

liam James lectures at Harvard; in 1937,


the Richards lectures at the University of

Virginia,

and

in 1940, the

Mahlon Powell

lectures at the University of Indiana.

He

is

founder and director of Archives

d'Htstoire Doctrinale et Litteraire

du Moyen-

age (with R.P.G. Thery) of which 16 vol-

umes have been published


de Philosophie

since 1925; Etudes

Me die vale,

35 volumes since

1921; Etudes de Tbeologie et d'Histoire de


la Spiritualite,

9 volumes since 1934, and


at the Pontifical

founder (with colleagues


Institute of

Mediaeval Studies) of Mediaeval

Studies, of

which 9 volumes have been pub-

lished since 1939-

Professor Gilson

is

member

of the

French Academy, the Royal Academy of


Holland, the British Academy, the American Academy of Arts and Sciences and the
Pontifical
at

Academy of

St.

Thomas Aquinas

Rome.

He

has

received

many honorary

de-

grees: Doctor

of Letters (D.Litt.)

from Ox-

ford University; Doctor of Laws (LL.D.)

from the University of Aberdeen, Harvard


University and the University of Pennsylvania; Doctor of Philosophy (Ph.D.)

from

Rome, University of Milan and the University

of Montreal.

He
lic

is

president of the Franco-Canadian

Institute, president

of the Society of Catho-

Authors

at Paris, a

member

of the Se-

cours Catholique International and of Pax

Romana, before which he has

lectured in

Rome.
Professor Gilson entered the Conseil de
la

Republique, the upper house or senate

of the present French government in 1946.

He was
same

technical adviser to the French dele-

gation to the San Francisco Conference that


year,

composing the French

text of

the Charter of the United Nations.


also a French delegate to

He was UNESCO, the


Scientific

United Nations Educational,

and

Cultural Organization, for which he also

wrote the French

text.

Professor Gilson has published the

fol-

lowing volumes up to December 1947:


hidex
scolastico-cartesien,
Paris,
print.

Alcan,

1913, ix and 355 pages.

Out of

La Liberte chez Descartes


Paris, Alcan, 1913,

et la theologie,

453 pages. Out of

print.

Etudes de philosophie medievale.


lection des travaux

Col-

de

la Faculte des lettres

de Strasbourg, Strasbourg,
291 pages. Out of print.

1921,

v'm and

La

'Philosophie

de Saint Bonaventure,

Paris, Vrin, 1st edition, 1924,

420 pages; 2nd

edition, 1943,

483 pages;

1st edition translat-

ed under the

title

of The Philosophy of Saint

Bonaventure, Sheed
1938,
xiii

&

Ward,

New

York,

and 551 pages.

Discours de la Methode (Descartes) edited

with commentary, Paris, Vrin,

1st edi-

tion 1925,

2nd edition 1939,

text 78,

com-

mentary 490 pages.

Saint

Thomas d'Aquin, (Les


and coinmentary,

moralists
Paris,

Chretiens) texts

Ga-

balda, 6th edition 1941, 380 pages, translat-

ed under the

title
St.

of Moral Values and the

Moral

Life,

Louis

&

London, Herder,

1931, 329 pages.

Etudes sur

le role

de la pensee medtevale
cartesien, Paris,

dans la formation de systeme


Vrin, 1930, 345 pages.

UEsprit de la philosophie medievale (the


Gifford lectures of 1930-31) Paris, Vrin, 1st
edition, 2 vols.,

1932; 2nd edition,

vol.,

1944, 447 pages; translated under the

title

of

The

Spirit of Aiediaeval Philosophy,


1 vol.,

New

York, Scribners, 1936,

484 pages.
Paris,

Les Idees

et

les

Lettres,

Vrin,

1932, 300 pages.

Pour un ordre catholique,


de Brouv^^er, 1934, 237 pages.

Paris,

Desclee

La Theologie mystique de
Paris, Vrin, 1934,

Saint Bernard,

251 pages; translated un-

der the

title

of The Mystical Theology of

St.

Bernard,

New

York, Sheed

&

Ward,

1940,

264 pages.
Saint

Thomas Aquinas, from

Proceed-

ings of the British Academy, Vol.

XXI, Lon-

don,

Humphrey

Milford, 1935, 19 pages.


Paris, P. Tequi,

Le Realisme methodique,
1936, 101 pages.

Christianisme et philosophie, Paris, Vrin,


1936, 168 pages, out of print; translated un-

der the

title

of Christianity and Philosophy,

New York,

Sheed

& Ward,

1939, 134 pages.

The Unity of Philosophical Experience


(the William James lectures of 1937)

New

York, Scribners, 1937, 331 pages.


Mediaeval Universalism and
Value
1936)
pages.
Its

Present

(Harvard Tercentenary Conference

New

York, Sheed

&

Ward,

1937, 22

Reason and Revelation

in

the Middle

Ages (the Richards

lectures of 1937)

New

York, Scribners, 1938, 110 pages.

Helo'ise

et

Abelard, Paris, Vrin, 1938,

252 pages.
Realisme thomiste
et critique

de la con-

naissance, Paris, Vrin, 1939,

239 pages; soon

to be translated into English.

Dante

et

la

philosophie,

Paris,

Vrin,

1939, X and 341 pages.

God and
tures of 1940)
Press,

Philosophy (the Powell

lec-

New

Haven, Yale University


Press,

and Oxford, Oxford University

1941, 144 pages.

Introduction a
Paris,

l'

etude de Saint Augustin,


1929,
ii

Vrin,

1st

edition,

and 352

pages; 2nd edition 1943, 352 pages; soon


to

be translated into English.

La Philosophie an moyen-age,
Payot, 2nd
edition, 1944,

Paris,

763 pages, soon to

be translated into English. Theologie


et histoire

de

la spiritualite,

Paris, Vrin, 1943,

27 pages.

Le Thomisme,

Paris, Vrin,

5th edition

1945, 523 pages; 3rd edition translated under


the
title

of The Philosophy of
St.

St.

Thomas

Aquinas,

Louis, Herder, 1941; 362 pages;

5th edition soon to be translated into English.

Philosophic

et

Incarnation selon Saint

Augustin

(Conference

Albert

le

Grand,

1947), Montreal, Institut D'Etudes Medievales Universite

de Montreal, 1947, 55 pages.


of

L'P.tre et I'essence is in the process

being published by Vrin, Paris, 1948.

Being and Some Philosophers

is

sched-

uled to be published by MacMullen,

New

York, in 1948.

To

these the Aristotelian Society takes

pleasure in adding History of Philosophy

and Philosophical Education.

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY AND PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION

History of Philosophy and


Philosophical Education

THE
the
entails

very

name

of philosophy means

love
is

of wisdom.
to

To

philoso-

phize, then,

pursue wisdom through

a consistent effort of reflexion, which itself


definite

ethical

requirements;

for

indeed no
time,

man

can, at

one and the same

both philosophize and indulge in


life as are

such ways of

incompatible with

philosophical thinking.

Yet even suppossatis-

ing that these moral conditions are


fied,

the fact remains that, by


is

its

very nature,

a philosopher's life

a constant effort to

acquire wisdom.

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY AND


But what
is

wisdom? According
it

to

its

classical definition,

is

the

knowledge of
first

the

first

principles
it

and of the

causes.

Of

course,

includes the knowledge of

many

other things as well; but in so far as he


is

using his wisdom, a wise

man knows
first

all

the rest as included in, or at least, related


to the first principles

and the

causes.
as to

We

are not without


this

some experience

what

means. There are things which


because

we know

we remember

them, and

there are things

which we know, not because

we remember

them, but because

some other things

we know through which we can


if

always find them again

need be, without

burdening our memory with cumbersome

and unnecessary
tellect thus

details.

Every time our

in-

succeeds in substituting some

principles

and causes of knowledge for


itself, it is

knowledge

on the right road


fact,
it

to

wisdom. As a matter of

has already

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION
found wisdom,
at least in part,

while await-

ing the day when, fully aware of what the


absolutely
truly are,
first
it

principles

and the

first

causes

begins to see everything else in

their light.
If
this

be

true,

philosophy

is

less

knowledge than
suit
ly,

a life dedicated to the pur-

of a definite type of knowledge, name-

wisdom.

It is a

rather peculiar sort of


is

occupation and a life-long one. This


there are so

why
I

few philosophers, by which


entire lives are
to

mean men whose

wholly
task

and ultimately dedicated

the

of

achieving wisdom. True enough, most


are fond of saying,

men

from time

to time, that

they too are philosophers.


their

And

they are, in

own

way, inasmuch

as,

through a long

experience of things and men, plus a certain

amount of

reflexion,

they

have reached

some general conclusions which they call


their philosophy.

Yet they are not philoso-

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY

AND

phers, precisely because their so-called phi-

losophy has grown spontaneously out of


their lives,

whereas a philosopher's

life is

completely dedicated to the conquest of wis-

dom.

If

one

is

a philosopher,

he can do
or,
it

nothing else than philosophize;


does something
else,

if

he

he will do

with a

view

to securing the
I

freedom he needs for


I

philosophizing.
if,

hope

will not startle

you

the better to
I

make

clear

what

have in

mind,

say that even professors of philos-

ophy are not philosophers. Some of them

may

be, but not all,

nor always. For indeed,

teaching philosophy and philosophizing are


far

from being one and the same


If it is

thing.

thinking aloud, the teaching of

philosophy
ion; but
reer
is
it

may help

philosophical reflexif

will not help

one's teaching ca-

spent in repeating by rote the very


philosophical

same

formulas,

and

this

sometimes for twenty years or more.

To

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION
truly great philosopher, teaching
is

a nui-

sance, or, at least, a lesser evil. His professorial position is to

him, of

all positions,

the

one that enables him


the slightest possible

to earn a living

with

damage

to his true
is

philosophical

life.

While he

teaching,

he

is

perhaps not philosophizing, but, at

least,

he

is

talking about philosophy.

Such

an avocation takes him away from philos-

ophy

as

little

as

possible.
calls

This

is

what
aliis

Thomas Aquinas
tradere.

contemplata

Yet,
to act,

when

all is said

and done,
is

to to

teach

is

whereas

to philosophize

contemplate, and though, in this one instance, the active life of a

man

is

but the
these
their

overflowing of his contemplative

life,

two

lives

are not the same.


different.

Even
It is

proximate objects are

one

thing, for instance, to speculate about the

relations of being to becoming,

and

it

is

quite another thing to prepare twenty pu-

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY

AND

pils for their final

examination at the end of

the year.

At the very same time when Bergfirst-year

son was teaching


college,

philosophy in
his cele-

he was engaged in writing


Essay

brated

on the Immediate Data of


Yet, had he attempted to

Consciousness.
teach his pupils

what he himself was

perall

sonally then interested in, they

would

have failed

their examinations, and,

how-

ever great a philosopher he might have

been, he

may

very well have lost his job. In


those of us

point of

who have seen copy-books of his college lectures, know that his course was pretty much the same as
fact,

that of

any ordinary professor of philoscontained sound and well ordered

ophy.

It

information about psychology, methodology, ethics and -metaphysics, in accord with


the

requirements
official

and the order of the

French

program.

Now such as it was,

Bergson's course v/as a very good introduc-

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION
tion to philosophy indeed; but there

were

many

other teachers, at the very same time,


exactly the

who were doing


course under his
losopher,- he

same

thing. It

would be betraying him

to publish such a
since, as a phi-

own name,

had very

little to

do with

it. I

once met a captain in the French army

who

had been a pupil of Bergson's


early courses. Naturally,
sort of professor
I

in

those

asked him what

Bergson was.

"A wonderafter a

ful one,"

came the answer. Then,

brief pause, the captain

added with a smile:

"But, of course,

we
is

did not

know he was
to

Bergson." That

why, even though your

professor of philosophy
also a philosopher,

may happen
as such in

be

you do not know him


your

and you do not meet him


classrooms.

He

is

a philosopher, not

when

he

is

speaking to you but during those hours

of solitude

when he

is

speaking to himself
meditation.

in the quietness of his

own

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY
This
raises a rather

AND

puzzling problem

for those

who want
still
it.

to study philosophy

and perhaps
it is

more

for those
is

whose work
the occupa-

to teach

If

philosophy

tion of a life time,

how

can

it

be learned or

taught within three or four or five years?

Should

we

not even ask:


all ?

how

can

it

be

learned or taught at

According to what

we

said a
is

moment

ago, the quest of wis-

dom

a personal affair. If

wisdom
its

is

to

be your

own wisdom, own


knows
quest.

then

quest must
that

be your
teacher
it is

The
and

fact
tells

your

truth

you what
it

does not mean that you


it

know

too;

but however long

takes you to realize

the meaning of his words,

when you

do,

you know truth exactly


truth
is

as

he does, and that


is his. It

yours exactly as his truth

may be
knows

the same truth, but every one


it,

who
intel-

knows

it

through his

own

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION
lect,

so

that,

ultimately,

he

is

his

own

teacher.

Such

is,

as

believe, the

meaning of

St.

Augustine's
clusion
is

De

Magistro, a

work whose

conelse

that

no one teaches any one

anything.

Yet, all over the world, pupils


bitter experience

and students know from


that this
is

too

good

to

be
at

true. If

it

were

true, all teachers


jobs.

would

once lose their

They

don't, or, at least,


is

when one

of

them does, he
one;
so
that,

at

once replaced by another

on the whole, everything


in fact,

happens

as

though teachers were,

doing something.

And what
what

they do can

be learned from Thomas Aquinas who,


happily

completing

St.

Augustine

has said on this point, observes that teachers,

though they cannot think for

us,

can

yet

make

us think for ourselves, or, at

least,
se-

help us in so doing. Through carefully


lected words,

which are the signs of

his

10

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY
concepts and his

AND

own

own

judgments, a
rise to similar

competent teacher can give


concepts

and

similar

judgments

in

the

minds of

his pupils.
is

What

pupils learn

from

their teachers

not necessarily what


it is

their teachers think; rather,

what they
say.

understand from what their teachers

This

is

where

St.

Augustine was right: no


his

one can know anything except through

own
may

mind. Yet the misunderstandings that


arise

can be avoided, corrected, and

finally eliminated.

When
in

a teacher has at
his his

length

succeeded
to

making

thought clear
pupils,

one or several of
his

own own
intel-

he has not substituted

own

lect for theirs,

but he has certainly taught

some one something.

How,

then,

is

the teacher going to teach


are not here concerned

philosophy?

We

with the technical details of philosophical

pedagogy. Obviously, there are as many

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION
good ways of teaching philosophy
are

11

as there

good professors of philosophy, and


different their

however
are

ways may

be, if they
all
is

good

professors, their
at the

ways are

good.

Our main concern

moment
is

with a

much wider problem: what

the best apit

proach to philosophy? Here, again,

can

be said that there are several good ones, and


that

what

is

good

for

some students may


dif-

not be quite as good for students of a


ferent kind.

But,

in

the end,

and even
to try

though a professor were successively


different

approaches
try

to

philosophy,
at a time;

he

could

still

them only one

and

the only justification he could feel in try-

ing any one of them

is

that

it is,

or at least

might be, the best approach

to philosophy.

Our

question, therefore, remains:

what

is

this best

approach to philosophy going to


shall
.^

be,
it

and for what reasons

we

consider

as better than

any other

12

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY AND

One

of Descartes' friends once asked


to him, his

him how, according

own

son

should be taught philosophy.


tion

To
a

this ques-

the

philosopher

made
let

surprising

answer.

He

did not say:


let

him read my

own

works; he said:
it

your son learn

philosophy as

is

being taught in the


is,

schools of the Jesuits, that


the

by taking

whole course

in

philosophy from bevery well

ginning to end.

Now we know

what such philosophical courses usually


are.

Cursus

philosophiae,

Compendium

philosophiae, Elementa philosophiae, philosophiae,

Summa
such
a

whatever

its

name,

book

is

supposed to give us a general survey

of philosophical problems as well as of their


possible solutions.

When

written from the


it

point of view of

Thomas Aquinas,

becomes

a Cursus philosophiae Thomisticae, a

Com-

pendium philosophiae ad mentem Ihomae


Aquinatis, or something of the sort. In
all

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION
cases,

13

works of

this

kind purport to be so
or,

many
if

"Introductions to Philosophy,"

they are both

more

clear sighted

and more

ambitious, they are so

many

"Initiations to

the Philosophical Life."

The

striking suc-

cess of this sort of philosophical literature

would be

unintelligible

if it

did not answer


it

a genuine need. In point of fact

does.

When
try,

person asks us to describe a counis

the best answer to give


is

to

show him

map. This
it is

not the best ultimate answer,


first

but

the best

one; and in so far as

introductions to philosophy are concerned,


their greatest merit
is

to be
still
is

both maps

of,

and guides
the

to,

what

for beginners

unknown country
It

of philosophy.
folly to act otherwise.

would be sheer
first

In the

place, not all those


will

who

study

philosophy

become
if

philosophers.

What

else

do they need
it

not to be

in-

formed, be

in a superficial

way, about

14

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY
nature,
its

AND
their cor-

its

main problems and

rect

solution? But even those beginners,

to

whom
way
on

such an introduction will open

the

to the true philosophical life, will


feel thankful for

later
it

having entered

in the

same way.
start

No

beginner should be

asked to

from

scratch, as

though phi-

losophy had not begun to exist twenty-four


centuries ago,

and nothing had ever been


it.

said or written about

True enough, our

problem may appear somewhat more simple


if

what we want

to

do

is

to teach philosit

ophy ad mentem Thomae Aqutnatis; but


actually
is

not.

No work

of

Thomas
in

Aquinas has been written for beginners


philosophy, and

when he wrote
from being
is

his philo-

sophical treatises or commentaries, he himself

was very

far

a beginner so true that,


to

writing for beginners. This

from the thirteenth century down

our

own

day,

innumerable commentaries on

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION
St.

15

Thomas have been


many

written which are

intended as so

introductions to the

personal reading of his


are probably the reasons
at
least

own

works.

Such

similar

oneswhich

or, if

not these,

prompted
scholastic

Descartes, the sworn

enemy of
a

philosophy

to

recommend

complete

course in scholastic philosophy as the best


introduction to philosophical knowledge.

This was a very sound piece of advice, and

one that
today.

it

would be very wise

to give even

Let us suppose, now, that such advice has

been wisely given and wisely accepted.

Where

does

this lead

us? After receiving


philosophy, some

this first introduction to

beginners will quit, and they will be by far


in the majority
;

a few others will wish to go

on, and these are the only ones in

whom
they to

we should now be

interested.

Were

16

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY

AND
we answer

ask us what to do,

how

should

them?

A first way to answer their question might


be to suggest another introduction to philosophy.

For introductions are plentiful,


identical.
Still bet-

and no two of them are


ter,

after a truly elementary one,

we might
the time
a

suggest a series of progressively more and

more

difficult introductions, until

comes for the student, by now no longer


beginner,
to

apply

to

those

specialized

books that deal with the particular problems which interest him.
far

Now

am

very

from finding

fault with such a peda-

gogical method.

The only

question which

concerns

me

is,

what notion of philosophy

such a method entails.


I

And

the only answer

can imagine

is

that, for those

who hold

such a

way of

learning philosophy as wholly


practically
self-sufiicient,

satisfactory

and

philosophy probably appears as a science

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION
essentially

17

similar

to

other

sciences

and

hence capable of being taught in exactly the

same way.

Is

not a science a body of cogni-

tions related to the

same

object, rationally

demonstrable and therefore communicable

by means of teaching? Such

are,

for in-

stance, mathematics, physics, chemistry

and
rea-

biology.

And one

fails to see for

what

son philosophy,

if it is

a science,

should not

likewise be taught and learned as are the

other sciences, that

is

to say,

through introits

ducing beginners to
ods and
its

its

problems,

meth-

present conclusions.

The

better to answer this question, let

us ask another one. In

what sense
the

is

such a

pedagogical method
teach the sciences?

proper way to
is:

The ready answer


is

to

the full extent to which a science

made up

of already acquired results.

You

can learn

physics from oral lectures or from printed


text books; but even after personally check-

18

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY AND

ing your thus acquired learning by conducting suitable experiments in the laboratory,

what are you

fitted to

become? Perhaps

useful engineer, or a

good professor of

physics; but a physicist, no.

learned

man
a

conversant with science, yes. But a


no. Professors of history

scientist,

may may

well

know

great deal of history, they

all

be scholars,
So,

yet very few of them are historians.


too,

we may come

to

know

a great deal

about the physics or the philosophy of our time without necessarily being either
physicists or philosophers.

As with

intro-

ductions to the other sciences, so in the case

of philosophy: where philosophy begins,


introductions to philosophy should

come

to

an end.
at all,
is

What

then begins,

if it is

to begin

a really

new

experience, something

as radically different

from what went

be-

fore

it

as being a great professor of English


is

literature

different

from being a Shake-

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION
speare.
to

19

Not merely

to learn philosophy, but


this is

become a philosopher,

what

is

now

at stake. It

does not involve giving up phiit

losophy as a science;

rather involves aim-

ing at possessing philosophy in a different

and more exalted way

as included in wisin the

dom

itself, to

which

it is

same

rela-

tion as a

body

to its soul.

Then

also does the


its

philosophical life truly begin, and

begin-

ning does not consist in any addition to


already acquired learning;
like falling in love, like
it

rather looks
call

answering the

of a vocation, or undergoing the transform-

ing experience of a conversion.


I

am

not here describing the self-revelagenius, nor the birth

tion of

some powerful

of a great philosopher, whose writings will


later
field

be considered as a landmark in the


of philosophy.

One cannot

create in

philosophy unless he be a true philosopher;


but one can live and die a true philosopher

20

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY

AND

without having created anything philosophical.

"Without his creative genius, a great

philosopher would remain at least a philosopher.

The

difference,

however, which
to

am

trying to describe

is less

be found

in

some
in
its

exceptional quality of the

mind than

desire to achieve an active

and personal
truth.

appropriation
the

of philosophical

In

mind of

man born

to the philosophi-

cal life, ideas

do not merely follow one anin

other, be

it

logical

sequence, as they
first

do when we read them for the


a

time in

book; they are not simply associated by

the process of reasoning and the

demands
fall

of demonstration; they do not merely


into place as so

many

pieces of a cleverly

contrived puzzle, but one


that

would

rather say

they blend into

an organic whole,
life

quickened from within by a single

and

able spontaneously to assimilate or reject

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION
the spiritual food offered to the laws of
its
it,

21

according to

own

inner development.
destined to be great or

Whether he be
to

remain unknown within the rank and


a

file,

philosopher

once born has

still

to

grow.
this

He

still

needs to be taught,

not

time philosophy, but to philosocan help him in his need,

phize.
if

And who

not another philosopher

who
a

will

be

for

him both a master and


life?
is

companion
of

during his whole


all

The most urgent


to find such a

problems, then,
this
is

man,

and

far

from

easy; for in order to be

a master, a philosopher should be great,

and

great philosophers are scarce.


countries, like Russia,

Very large

have never seen one;

and how many have been born, since the


discovery of America, between Alaska and

Patagonia ?
his

Not

every Plato can hope to find

own Socrates, nor every Aristotle his own Plato. During the whole French eigh-

22

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY

AND

teenth century, the so-called "century of

philosophers," there was not a single great

philosopher.

Nor

does the problem stop here.


affinity

Is

not a certain spiritual

required be-

tween master and disciple?


learn

If in

order to

how

to walk,

we need

to

follow some-

one, at least for a time,


to find a guide

it is

useless for us

who

can show us

how

to

do
the
to

it,

unless both of us wish to walk


find
it

down
hard

same road. Some persons


discover a
religious

director
cases

of con-

science, yet there are

no

where the

thing cannot be done. Finding

among our

contemporaries a philosophical director of


conscience
so
that,
is

infinitely

harder

still

so

much

however anxiously a man may

search, there are

many

places and times


is

when, for him, such


lutely impossible.

a discovery

abso-

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION

23

Yet, on second thought, such advisers


are

many and always

at

hand,

if

not in the

present, at least in the past;

and since

we
Of

are dealing with philosophy,

what

diflfer-

ence

is

there between past and present ?

their very nature,

metaphysics and ethics

deal with problems that wholly escape time.

Twenty-four centuries ago,


been said that being
that
is

it

had already
is

and non-being

not;

what undergoes becoming and change

does not truly deserve to be said to be; that


the two foundations of society are justice

and

friendship,
is

because

without

justice

friendship
ship justice

blind, just as without friend-

is sterile.

Of

these three prop-

ositions, is there a single

one which, during

the last twenty-four centuries, has for a single

moment

ceased to be true? If our


fail us, therefore, let

own

contemporaries

us look
need.

into the past for the master that

we

Perhaps he

is

there, patiently waiting for

24

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY
tell

AND
we

us to

him our own troubles and ask


questions.

him our own


hesitate?

Why

should

No
it is

intelligible relation

between

any two terms ever belongs


every time
ent.

in the past;

understood,

it is

in the pres-

This

is

also the point at

which the

his-

tory of philosophy enters the picture as part

and parcel of philosophical education


that
is,

provided the professors of philoshistory to

ophy allow
not,

come

in.

Many do

and not without some appearance of


have heard some say that the
is,

justification. I

goal of a truly philosophical education

not to

know

what other

men have thought

in the past, but

what

man

should think
will say

now. And there are others who


that the history of philosophy
is

but the

common
and

graveyard of dead philosophies,

that living philosophers should let the


their dead.

dead bury

Yet there

is

more

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION
serious objection. It
is

25

many

centuries
is

now
said

since Cicero said that there

nothing so

foolish

and so vain which has not been

by some philosopher. Descartes,


history under all
its

who

hated

forms, was fond of

quoting

this saying;

whence many profes-

sors of philosophy conclude that teaching

the history of philosophy

amounts

to noth-

ing more than teaching a comprehensive


collection of all possible errors.

Now,

to

teach philosophy

is,

or at least should be,


it

something very

different;

should be noth-

ing less than the teaching of philosophical


truth.

Perhaps

it

might be useful

to

quote

erroneous positions in order to refute them,


but

why should we invite

a young and inex-

perienced mind to lose


est of errors
?

itself in

such a for-

we know that Spinoza and Hegel were wrong, why should we let the
If

young student read Spinoza and Hegel ?


might
as well feed

We

him poison. However

26
this

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY

AND
is

may
it is

be,

one thing

at least

certain,

and
not

that the history of philosophy can-

but

breed philosophical

scepticism.

Thus

tossed without sail or wheel

on a

sea

of conflicting opinions, a well-made

mind

can do but one thing with philosophy, and


that
I is

to give

it

up

as a

bad

job.

have no intention of dismissing these

objections as

weak

or irrelevant.

They

are

strong and very


theirs,

much

to the point, but to


all

not

ours.

They

derive

their

strength from the same notion of philos-

ophy, conceived as a ready-made science,

whose

results

have to be taught. Now, as


is

has already been said, there

such a science,

and since

it

should be both learned and

taught, the only

way

to

do

it

is

the

way

that befits any science, namely, the dog-

matic way.

If a
is

man

does not think he


is

knows what

true

and what

not true in
it.

philosophy, he has no business to teach

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION
As
a matter of fact,
I

27

many

do, but they

should not; and

suppose

we would
is

all

agree that just as to teach physics

to teach
is

true physics, so to teach philosophy

to

teach true philosophy.


foolish thing indeed

It

would be a very
introduce young

to

minds

to

philosophy through the indiscrim-

inate reading of texts

which they cannot un-

derstand or,

if

they do, against which they

are defenseless

as

we

all

are in those dis-

cussions in which, wholly ignorant of the

business at hand,

we

experience the uneasy


is

feeling that .the last speaker

always right.

But

this is

not at

all

our problem.
is

What

we

are

now

looking for

a master, a com-

panion and a guide in our


cal quest of

own

philosophi-

wisdom, and because

we

fail to

find

one

in the present

we have

to turn to

the past.

Thus did once the Alttssimo

poeta,

when

seeing himself without any one

who

could teach him to become a poet, he went

28

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY AND

back more than a thousand years and found


Vergil.

We

do not need

to

go

as far

back

as that in order to find

Thomas Aquinas.
at

Yet,

when we meet him


if

long

last,

where

do we find him
can
tory

not in history?

And how
his-

we approach
?

him, except through

Here, as

believe,

is

the very root of

most of our misunderstandings concerning


the proper approach to philosophy. Let us

consider this simplest of

all

cases.

After

looking for help, some one reaches the conclusion that the best thing to do
is

apply to

Thomas Aquinas. He
ciple of
tent a Thomist.

thus becomes a disto that ex-

Thomas Aquinas, and

So far so good. But

how

does he

know

that

he

is

Thomist?
his first

Should we ask him the question,


answer might be:
because
I

"I

know

am

Thomist
is is

am

in

agreement with what


in

written in a

book

which philosophy

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION
taught ad

29

mentem Divi Thomae

Aquinatis."

And
then,

the answer

may happen

to

be right, but
his

how

does he

know

that

what
of

book

describes as

the philosophy

Thomas
Thomas'

Aquinas

is

a faithful rendering of

own thought?
make
sure
is

Obviously, the only

way

to

to

compare such a work with


himself. But just
this,

those of
as

Thomas Aquinas

soon as you undertake to do

you find

yourself engaged in straight historical work.

True enough,

history

is

not here your goal.


to

"What you ultimately want

know

is

truth,
is

but since your immediate problem

to

know

if

what Thomas Aquinas


first

says

is

true,

what you

must know
says.

is

what Thomas
it

Aquinas actually

Nor would
what
is

do

to

object that, so long as


is

in the

book

true,

you don't care whether Thomas


it

Aquinas said
simply

or

not;

for

this

would

mean

that

you are not a

disciple of

Thomas Aquinas, but

of some one else free-

30
ly

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY
using his name.
that he
is

AND

No

philosopher can

know

a Thomist unless he also

be an historian.
This
first

conclusion
it

is

rich in

many

imto

plications,

which

would be tedious

man who can tell us exactly what Thomas Aquinas has said, is Thomas Aquinas himself. In order to know what he said we must read
enumerate. For indeed, the only
his works.

But what works has he actually

written? "Where are the best manuscripts?


In these best manuscripts, what are, accord-

ing to

all probabilities,

the safest readings ?

Once v/e

feel reasonably sure of his text,

what

does that text

mean ? Many and voluminous


but they do not always
cases, they seriously dis-

commentaries have been written on the


Thomistic
texts,

agree, and, in agree.


that
to

some

Now,

if

we have made up

our minds

Thomas Aquinas found the true road wisdom, we need to know where his

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION
road
lies.

31

We
in a

are like people following

some one
that

crowd because they know

he

is

going where they wish to go, and

yet always

wondering where he
still

is.

It is

hard task

to find him, a

harder one not

to lose him,

and

it is

the historian's task.

No

wonder
to

that so

many philosophers
it.

decline

have anything to do with

Why should
is

they?

Perhaps they need no master, no

companion, no guide.

My

only point

that

unless they resort to history, they have


right to say they are following a guide
that the

no
and

name

of their guide

is

Thomas

Aquinas.

But these are minor points because,


all,

after

they are mainly material and, so to

speak, external to our problem.

That probis

lem
to

is

to

know why,

if

Thomas Aquinas
it

be our guide, he alone can do


else in his place.

and no

one

Now

let

us see what

may

actually

happen when works ad mentem

32

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY AND


are substituted for those of the
I

Dhi Thomae

Angelic Doctor.

am not here planning to deit; I

bate any issue and take sides in

rather

want

to

show

that there

may be

very big

issues involved,

and

that unless

we walk
away

carefully

we may

find ourselves miles

from our chosen guide and


ing another one

actually follow-

who

is

taking us where

we

do not wish

to go.

If there is a

fundamental notion in any


that of being.

philosophy,

it is

As one con-

ceives being, so
physics.

one will conceive metais

Now

there

a very simple experieasily

ment which anyone can

perform, pro-

vided only that some good philosophical


library

be at hand. All you need

to

do

is

to

take off the library shelves

some textbooks
Divt

of philosophy ad mentem

Thomae.

You

then open these books, one by one, to

the chapter that deals with the relation be-

tween essence and existence.

It

will not take

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION
you very much time
books
fall into

33

to discover that these


classes,
is

two

namely, those

which affirm that there


essence and existence in

a distinction of

re,

and those which

deny

it.

In other words, according to


is

some

of these text books, the world

made up
is

of real essences, whose existence

either a

mode

or

some other determination, while,


rest,

according to the

the world

is

made up
which

of essences actualized by a higher


is

act,

the act of existing.

Here are two philo-

sophically different worlds, for indeed beings cannot, at one and the

same time be

essences actualized by distinct acts of existing,

and essences not so


is

actualized.

What,

then,

supreme
is

in reality, essence or existit is,

ence ?
is?

What

supreme, what

or that

it

Obviously, a philosopher

is

here bound
is

to

make

a choice; the only thing that


is

not

possible

to

maintain that there

is

a phi-

losophy in which both of these views are

34

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY AND


and the same time. In point of

true at one
fact,

the authors of philosophies ad

mentem

Divi Thomae have no hesitation in making


their
dict
all

own

choices, but these choices contra-

one another

and yet
I

their authors are

Thomists.

Now

shall

not here

tell

you

what

my own choice would be, or, rather, what my own choice is. I could not possibly
do so because
to state
it,

it

would be sheer
it

arbitrariness

while to justify

would involve

us in endless historical demonstrations. But

one thing,

at least,

is

sure. It is this:

whichis

ever of the two parties to this discussion


right, the other

one

is

wrong.

Through
philos-

their wilful neglect of history,

many

ophers profess publicly to follow a certain


leader and then actually follow another

one; which

is

a refreshing spectacle, well

suited to bringing
solation.

poor historians some con-

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION

35

This slightly ludicrous confusion, however,

would not mean very much


names which
it

if

the mis-

take about

implies did not

presuppose a more serious mistake about


things.
ror,

Whoever

is

here committing an
is

er-

it is

a fact that he

mistaken about

the very nature of philosophy itself; and,

strangely enough, his mistake has,


again, something to

once

do with the

practical

requirements of teaching in schools.


torical

his-

example

will perhaps

make

clearer

what

have in mind. In the early decades of


century,

the nineteenth
official

there

existed

an

government program for French

faculties of philosophy. It

was a very simple

one: the doctrine to be taught by them was


that of Locke, with all suitable corrections.

Now my
sense
large
it
.'*

question very

is

this:

does this

make

am

much

afraid that, to a very

number of professors of philosophy

does

make

sense,

and

almost despair of

36

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY AND


clear

making
ter

why

it

does not. For, as a mat-

of
if

fact, that is
is

what everybody has

to

do

he

called

on

to give a course in phi-

losophy.

Whether

the philosopher

whom

he

is

following be Thomas Aquinas, Duns

Scotus, Locke,

Kant or Royce does not make

much

difference as concerns our


is that,

own

prob-

lem. For the trouble


sors of philosophy,

being profesto extract lec-

we have

ture courses in general philosophy out of

the works of philosophers,

who have
work of
is

them-

selves never written any such thing.

The
Aris-

nearest approach to
totle,

it is

the

whose encyclopedic nature


reasons why, at
all

one of
all

the

many

times and in

places, his philosophy has been so highly

prized by university professors. Yet even


to Aristotle,
just as

philosophy was his philosophy,

to

Locke philosophical truth was

identical with the views laid

down

in his

Essay on

Human

Understanding.

As an

ex-

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION

37

pression of a single organic thought, a philosopher's personal philosophy enjoys an

organic unity of
ficult,

its

own, which makes

it

dif-

not to say impossible, to expand or


it,

to curtail

to correct or to
it

remodel
to date

it,

with
to

a view to bringing

up

and

adapting

it

to the requirements of
If,

modern

classroom teaching.

in Locke's philos-

ophy, you correct any one of those conse-

quences which follow necessarily from his


principles,

you

are,

in

fact,

denying his
philosophy.

principles

and rejecting

his

When,

in the early thirteenth century, the

teaching of Aristotle's writings was forbid-

den donee corrigantur,

it

soon became ap-

parent that they would never be corrected.

They could not

be. It

was then

that
it

Thomas
was pos-

Aquinas did the only thing that


sible to do:

he created a new philosophy,

which would have staggered Aristotle had

38

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY AND


it,

he known

since

it

was no longer

his phi-

losophy but that of

Thomas Aquinas.
it,

Such

is,

as

see

the fundamental dis-

tinction that

we

should always observe bein philosophy

tween a text book

and a

philosophical treatise. Each of them serves


its

own

purpose, but their purposes are not

the same.

text

book

in philosophy, or

even any course of lectures written as a


text book, is

bound

to lack that organic

unity

and continuity of thought which

marks the works of authentic philosophical


reflexion.

Wondering about

the difference

between genius and talent

in music,

Robert

Schumann once came


in all

to the conclusion that


is

works of genius there

a golden

thread running throughout the whole and

holding
reason

it

together. This,

no doubt,

is

the

why

another musician, Igor Stra-

vinski, does not like to

be called a "com-

poser," nor his works "compositions."

And

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION
so
it is

39

also with philosophy.

Even when

they are not compiled, textbooks are com-

posed, whereas philosophies are born.

There

is

only one
it

way

to

prove

this,

but

no one can prove


proof
lies in a

to

anyone

else,

for the

personal experience which

history alone can give.


life

The proof

lies in a

spent in personal and intimate contact

with great philosophers.

Of

all

those

who

have learned philosophy only

in schools or
I

from books written only for schools

am

sorry to say that they have not the slightest

idea of

what the philosophical

life really is.

Not

unlike the innumerable students

who

spend years in learning Latin and never use


it

to read Vergil,

our students in philosophy

are introduced to a philosophical life which

very few of them will ever enter.

cannot

help wondering, however,


ber

if

a larger

num-

among them would not


life,

enjoy living a
if

genuinely philosophical

they were

40

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY
in

AND

warned
them
but a

due time that what we must teach


is

as philosophy

not yet philosophy,

way

to

it,

and that the only true masare, are the great

ters in

philosophy there

philosophers ?

For those

at least

among our

students

who have heard

the call of philosophy and


it,

are eager to answer

how

could

we have

the slightest hesitation?


fessors of philosophy,
if

What

are we, pro-

not students older

than our

own

students ?

We cannot be their
When
let
is

masters, since

we

are not masters.

our work with them has been completed,


us take them directly to him

who

our

own

master. Let us, henceforth, teach them

to learn with him,

and under him, not with

us and under us. True enough,

we

can

still

help them, but not as before.


is

Our new

task

to teach

them

to learn

from one greater


to
as

than ourselves, to read

Thomas Aquinas,
him

assimilate his thought, to think with

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION
a true philosopher does, that
is

41

with the

same standard of

scientific objectivity

and

accuracy, until the time

comes when the


appear to
its first

whole body of

his doctrine will

them shot through with the


principles.

light of

When

will that time

come?

No
to

one can

tell,

but certainly not before


is

many
and

years of study, for there


riches in philosophy.

no short road
it

Yet come

will,

when

it

does philosophy will shine before

their eyes in the purity of its essence.

And

because a greater than


abled them to share in
fail to

we

are will have en-

its life,

they shall not


its

recognize in

it

the true source of

intelligible beauty,

Wisdom

that "reacheth
all

from end

to

end mightily and ordereth

things sv/eetly." (Wis. VIII, 1)

That
taken,

is

why, unless

be greatly mis-

the history

of philosophy should

be recognized everywhere as an essential


part of a complete philosophical education.

42

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY
this I
is,

AND
ultimate

By

mean an education whose

goal

not to teach philosophy but to form

full-fledged philosophers.

And
is

just as in the

case of everything else that


is

good, there

a price that

we must

pay, so, too, here;


rate,

but the price


that price
is

is

worth paying. At any


it is

not what

said to be

by those
ill-

professors of philosophy who, in their

advised zeal for pure abstract speculation,


seek to frighten us
studies.

away from

historical

Even supposing, dato non concesso,

that all their intentions are always wholly

pure, their reasons

would

still

not be valid,

since they completely miss the point.

The

history of philosophy cannot be a graveyard

for dead philosophers, because in philos-

ophy there are no dead. Owing


all

to history,
alive,

great philosophers are


is

still

and

none of them
vitality

showing signs of greater

than our master, companion and

guide,

St.

Thomas Aquinas. Nor

is

the his-

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION

43

tory of philosophy a school for scepticism.

Quite the contrary.

If there

is

a source of

philosophical scepticism to be found any-

where,

would

rather look for

it

in the

fatal illusion shared in

and widely spread

by

us, the professors

of philosophy, that our

introductions to the life of

wisdom
of

are
is

themselves wisdom.

The

life

wisdom

not to be found in them, the golden thread


of true philosophical thinking does not run,

unbroken, through their many parts, and


those of our students
life as

who

carry

them

into

dearly cherished treasures should be

ready for a distressing experience. Under


the
first

serious shock, the roughly

sown

parts of their philosophical patchquilt are

bound

to pull asunder.

The

very best thing


despairing

that can then

happen

is

that, in

of philosophy, they remember that

God
loss.

did

not choose to save


physics, so that
its

men through
be not their

meta-

loss

44

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY

AND

Would

it

not be more simple to clear


all,

up, once and for

the misunderstandings

that are here the source of so

many

probis

lems? Neither as science nor as wisdom

philosophy to be found outside some mind


of which
it is

a perfection, but

which

is its

cause. Philosophy has

no existence of

its

own

outside philosophers, and even that

superhuman wisdom which transcends time


is

given to us in time. Such also


in so far as

is

our

own wisdom
of

we have

one; such

were the wisdoms of Plato, of Aristotle and

Thomas Aquinas.
By

Like

men

themselves,

philosophies pass away, going the


all flesh.

way

of

a curious illusion,
is

we

like to

imagine that there

somewhere

in

this

world a philosophy subsisting


for
itself,

in itself

and

of which

all

philosophers are

equally invited to partake and in which they


freely share.

Why

not, then,
it

go a

little far-

ther

and imagine

as laid

down

in such

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION
books
as

45

contain, not the philosophy of

Plato, of Aristotle, or of

Thomas Aquinas,

that

is,

not someone's philosophy, but phi-

losophy pure and simple?

We may try,

but the trouble


is

is

that phi-

losophy pure and simple

a pure

and sim-

ple essence, not a being. If ens means habens


esse, a

philosopher
is

is

a being,

whereas philos-

ophy

not. Exactly, the only actual being


is

which philosophy may have

that of the

philosopher, so that the anonymity of phi-

losophy points

less to its universality

than

to its lack of actual entity.

What makes
is

philosophical truth to be universal

some-

thing quite different. For each and every

one of

us, the root

of what

is

universal in

him

is

identical with the very core of his

own personality. Through his intellect, every man is a person and through the same
intellect

he can see exactly the same truth

as

any other

man

can

see,

provided they

46

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY
intellects in the
else, lies

AND

both use their

proper way.

Here, and nowhere

the foundation

for the very possibility of a philosophta per-

ennis; for

it is,

not a perennial cloud floating

through the ages in some metaphysical


stratosphere, but the

permanent

possibility

for each and every

human being

to actualize

an essence through his


is

own

existence, that

to experience

again the same truth in the


intellect.

light of his
itself is

pwn

And

that truth

not an anonymous one. Even taken


absolute

in

its

and

self-subsisting
Its

form,
is

truth in itself bears a name.

name

God.

Once
is

these fantasies are dispelled, there

room

for a solid, consistent

and consoling
if

reality.

We

should, no doubt, grant that

there

is

no ready-made philosophy

to teach

and

to learn,

wisdom

is

the prize, not only

of a quest, but also of a conquest.

We

all

have to win

it

the hard way. Yet, in our

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION

47

common effort, none of us is alone. At the moment when we give up the mirage of a self-subsisting philosophy, we find
very
ourselves surrounded by the friendly com-

pany of the philosophers. They are


this

all

here,

very day, around us, ready to assist us


task,

in

our

provided only that

we

apply to

them for
there
is

help. In all that they have said,

nothing that cannot be of assistance

including, as

Thomas Aquinas
their

himself once
failures.

expressly

observed,

very

What
in

a historian of philosophy looks for


is

the history

not philosophy, but


it

its

source,

and because he cannot find


else than

any-

where

where

it is,

being himself
it

an existing man, the historian finds

in the

minds of other existing men.


friends with
ber,

He may make
their

them and, among

num-

choose to himself a particularly befirst

loved one because he

feels

and soon

comes

to

know

that the philosopher of his

48

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY

AND
many
Then
cen-

choice embarked before him,


turies ago,

upon the only path

that leads also


its

whither he himself wishes to go.

does the history of philosophy reach

own end and find its own philosophical reward. A new philosophical life has been
kindled by another philosophical
is

life.

There

nothing here to suggest the giving of


gift; rather,

some

an act answers an act and

an existence echoes another existence. In


such a spiritual birth, everything
is

both old

and new,

in time
is

and out of time.

What
ence ?

there for us to lose in lending

ourselves to such a transforming experiIt is

beyond the power of any human

master to add an inch to the stature of his


disciples.

But he can make even the smallest


fulfill at least their

among them
ness, just as

own

small-

he can help the greatest among

them

to achieve their

own

greatness. Is an

example necessary ?

Do

but remember

how

PHILOSOPHICAL EDUCATION

49

much

time and

toil

Thomas Aquinas

has

spent in commenting
Aristotle.

upon the writings of


at

That work was,

one and the

same

time, history of philosophy pure

and

simple, as well as the effort of a disciple

asking guidance from his master. Aristotle

was the master,

for

every

time he said

The Philosopher, Thomas Aquinas meant


Aristotle.

Yet so

little

did his apprenticeship


disciple,

hamper the personal genius of the


that

were we asked today:

Who

is

the Phi-

losopher.?

we would

unhesitatingly answer:

Thomas Aquinas.

THE AQUINAS LECTURES


Published by the Marquette University Press,

Milwaukee

3,

Wisconsin

St.

Thomas and
late

the Life of Learning (1937) by the


F.

Fr.

John
at

McCormick,

S.J.,

professor of

philosophy

Loyola University.

St.

Thomas and

the Gentiles (1938) by Mortimer

J.

Adier, Ph.D., associate professor of the philos-

ophy of law, University of Chicago.


St.

Thomas and

the

Greeks (1939)

by Anton C.

Pegis, Ph.D., president of the Pontifical Institute

of Mediaeval Studies, Toronto.

The

attire

and Functions of Authority (1940) by


Ph.D.,
professor

Yves

Simon,

of

philosophy,

University of Notre

Dame.
Fr.

St.

Thomas and Analogy (1941) by


University of Notre

Gerald B.

Phelan, Ph.D., director of the Mediaeval Institute,

Dame.
(1942) by

St.

Thomas and
the

the

Problem of Evil

Jacques Maritain, Ph.D., French Ambassador to

Holy

See.

First in series

(1937) $1.00;

ail

others $1.50.

Humanism and Theology (1943) by Werner


Ph.D.,
Litt.D.,

Jaeger,

"university"

professor,

Harvard

University.

The Nature and Origins of Scientism (1944) by


John Wellmuth,
S.J.,

Fr.

chairman of the Department

of Philosophy, Xavier University.

Cicero

in

the

(1945) by the

Courtroom of St. Thomas Aquinas late E. K. Rand, Ph.D., Litt.D.,

LL.D., Pope Professor of Latin, emeritus, Harvard


University.

St.

Thomas and Epistemology (1946) by

Fr. Louis-

Marie Regis, O.P., Th.L., Ph.D., director of the


Albert the Great Institute of Mediaeval Studies,
University of Montreal.

St.

Thomas and the Greek Moralists (1947, Spring) by Vernon J. Bourke, Ph.D., professor of philosophy, St. Louis University, St. Louis, Mo.

History of Philosophy and Philosophical Education

(1947, Fall) by Etienne Gilson of the Academie


frangaise,

director

of studies

and professor of
Pontifical

the

history

of mediaeval philosophy,

Institute of

Mediaeval Studies, Toronto.

Uniform format, cover and binding.

Вам также может понравиться