Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 9

7.

4 Abbreviated Truth Tables

The full truth table method of Section 7.3 is extremely cumbersome. For example, an argument with only four statement letters requires a truth table with 24 = 32 rows. One with ve requires a truth table with 25 = 64 rows. Obviously, truth tables of these sizes are simply impractical to construct. Abbreviated truth tables provide a much more efcient method for determining validity.

The method
The key insight behind the method If we can construct just one row of a truth table for an argument that makes the premises true and the conclusion false, then we will have shown the argument to be invalid. If we fail at such an attempt, we will have shown the argument to be valid. Recall the argument from the lecture for 7.3:
Abortion is permissible only if fetuses are not innocent human beings or it is not always wrong to kill innocent human beings. But it is always wrong to kill innocent human beings. So abortion is not permissible. (A: Abortion is permissible; B: Fetuses are innocent human beings; W: It is always wrong to kill innocent human beings.)

We symbolized this sentence as follows: [A (B W)]. W A The method applied to an invalid argument 1. Write down the symbolized argument thus (note that weve dispensed with periods; they just get in the way): A (B W), W A

2. Hypothesize that the premises are true and the conclusion false: A (B W), T W A T F

3. Calculate the immediate consequences of this hypothesis:


Copy the truth value assigned to W to its other occurrence:

A (B W), T T

W A T F

Calculate truth values of the compound statements whenever you know the truth values of their component parts. Thus, we can calculate that W is false in virtue of our assumption that W is true:
2

A (B W), T FT

W A T F

Calculate truth values of the component parts of compound statements whenever you know the truth values of the compound statements (and copy any truth values assigned to statement letters to all other occurrences). Thus, we can calculate that A must be true given that A is false:

A (B W), T T FT

W A T FT

Furthermore, since (i) weve hypothesized that [A (B W)] is true and (ii) we have calculated that the antecedent A of [A (B W)] must be true (given our initial hypothesis about A), it now follows that (B W) must be true as well, lest we falsify our hypothesis that [A (B W)] is true. (Recall that a conditional is false if its antecedent is true and its consequent is false.) Hence:

A (B W), T T T FT

W A T FT

But now that we have deduced that the disjunction (B W) must be true (given our initial hypotheses), we know that, because its right disjunct W is false, its left disjunct B must be true for a disjunction is true if and only if at least one of its disjuncts is. Thus:

A (B W), T T T T FT

W A T FT
3

And this, of course, enables us now to deduce that B is false, which completes the row:

A (B W), T T TF T FT

W A T FT

So we have identied a row that makes the premises of our argument true and the conclusion false, so we have thereby demonstrated that the argument is invalid when A is true, B is false, and W is true. We complete the abbreviated truth table by recording this invalidating truth value assignment into the table:

A B W A (B W), T F T T T TF T FT
Much shorter than the full truth table! To remind you:

W A T FT

A T T T T F F F F

B T T F F T T F F

W A (B T F F T F F T T T F T T T T F T F F T T T F T T

W), F F T T T F T T F F T T T F

W A T F F F T F F F T T F T T T

Note that row 3 is exactly the row that we just constructed using the abbreviated truth table method.
4

The method applied to a valid argument


What happens if the argument in question is valid ? We demonstrate with a further example. Well cut right to the chase with a symbolized argument without worrying about the English argument it symbolizes. We begin with the usual hypothesis that the premises are true and the conclusion false:

W J, T

(W Z) (J Z), T

Z (W J) T F

Since the conclusion (W J) is false, its component statement (W J) must be true:

W J, T

(W Z) (J Z), T

Z (W J) T F T

From the truth table schema for , the only way for (W J) to be true is if both W and J are true. So we record this information below the conclusion, and copy it into the rest of the table:

W J, T T T

(W Z) (J Z), T T T

Z (W J) T F T T T

So far so good. Now, from the fact that Z is true, we infer that Z is false, and record this information into the table:

W J, T T T

(W Z) (J Z), T F T T F

Z (W J) TF F T T T
5

This then enables us to ll in the truth values for the two disjuncts in the second premise in accordance with the truth table schema for conditions:

W J, T T T

(W Z) (J Z), T F F T T F F

Z (W J) TF F T T T

But now there is a problem: our hypothesis was that the three premises were all true. But the second premise is a disjunction with two false disjuncts. Hence, it is itself false. But this conicts with our initial hypothesis. Hence, we have shown that it is not possible after all for the premises of the argument to be true and the conclusion false. We indicate the contradiction that arises when we assume otherwise by putting T/F underneath the main logical operator of the problematic premise (all of them, if there are more than one):

W J, T T T

(W Z) (J Z), T F F T/F T F F

Z (W J) TF F T T T

When there are several ways the conclusion can be false


If the conclusion can be made false in more than one way, then every way must be tried until either an invalidating assignment is found or all the ways of making the conclusion false are exhausted. Again, we start with the usual hypothesis:

B A, T

C D, T

A C B D T F

But note that, by the truth table schema for , there are three ways to make the conclusion false. So we simply pick one of the three to start with, viz., the one where both B and D are false:
6

B A, T

C D, T

A C B D T F F F

Copying these to the rest of the row and calculating truth values we get:

B A, TF T

C D, T F

A C B D T F F F

Because of the truth table schema for and our hypothesis that (C D) is true, it follows that C has to be false as well:

B A, TF T

C D, F T F

A C B D T F F F

Copying this value to (A C) we get

B A, T F T

C D, F T F

A C B D T F F F F

But now we see that there will be no way to make (A C) true, since one of its conjuncts is false. Consequently, this particular way of making the conclusion false fails to yield an invalidating assignment, and we so indicate:

B A, TF T

C D, F T F

A C B D T/F F F F F

Note: The Web Tutor will require you to complete the row. To do so, just assign an arbitrary value to A (it wont matter because (A C) will be false either way just because C is); F is easiest in this case:

B A, TF T TF

C D, F T F

A C B D F T/F F F F F

Now we need to try the two remaining ways of making the conclusion false; we will (arbitrarily) try the one where B is true and D is false rst:

B A, TF T TF T

C D, F T F T

A C B D F T/F F F F F T T F F

But, when calculated out, this possibility fares no better than the rst:

B A, TF T TF FT T FT

C D, F T F T T/F F

A C B D F T/F F F F F T T T T F F

So we must try the nal case, where B is false and D is true:

B A, TF T TF FT T FT T

C D, F T F T T/F F T

A C B D F T/F F F F F T T T T F F T F F T

But, when calculated out, this possibility too fails to yield an invalidating assignment:

B TF FT TF

T T T

A, TF FT TF

C D, F T F T T/F F T T T

A C B D F T/F F F F F T T T T F F F T/F T F F T

Only now that we have exhausted the possible ways of making the conclusion false are we permitted to say that the argument is valid; for on all the possible ways of making the conclusion false we found we were unable to make the premises true. If, however, any of these ways of making the conclusion false had yielded a row with true premises, the argument would have been shown to be invalid. To emphasize: to show invalidity, all it takes is one row, one truth value assignment to the statement letters, on which the premises are true and the conclusion false.

Вам также может понравиться